1 00:00:00,210 --> 00:00:04,650 OK, well, welcome to the series of mini podcasts. Welcome to everyone here. 2 00:00:04,650 --> 00:00:08,970 Thank you for coming and welcome to everyone watching on podcast. 3 00:00:08,970 --> 00:00:15,570 So today we are going to do the third one in the logic series and this time we're going to do induction. 4 00:00:15,570 --> 00:00:19,890 So for an argument to be good, it's conclusion. 5 00:00:19,890 --> 00:00:25,470 We you'll remember from one of the other podcasts, there's follow from its premises. 6 00:00:25,470 --> 00:00:34,110 But we saw in an earlier podcast that there are two sorts of following from a deductive argument. 7 00:00:34,110 --> 00:00:36,960 The conclusion follows from the premises. 8 00:00:36,960 --> 00:00:46,710 If the argument is valid and you'll remember if it's valid, that's because if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. 9 00:00:46,710 --> 00:00:57,090 But in an inductive argument, the conclusion follows the premises if the truth of the premises raises the probability of the truth of the conclusion. 10 00:00:57,090 --> 00:01:05,520 So whereas in a deductive argument, if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true in an inductive argument, 11 00:01:05,520 --> 00:01:12,000 the premises can be true without the conclusions having to be true to all the premises, 12 00:01:12,000 --> 00:01:18,180 to all the truth of the premises does raise the probability of the truth of the conclusion. 13 00:01:18,180 --> 00:01:28,020 So inductive arguments, whereas validity is an either or thing, inductive strength is a is a matter of degree. 14 00:01:28,020 --> 00:01:34,770 So here's a very weak inductive argument. Every time I've seen Marianne, she's been wearing earrings. 15 00:01:34,770 --> 00:01:38,700 I'm seeing Marianne tomorrow. Marianne will be wearing earrings tomorrow. 16 00:01:38,700 --> 00:01:44,490 Well, tomorrow, Saturday maybe I have a day off from wearing earrings on the Saturday. 17 00:01:44,490 --> 00:01:50,610 And here's a strong inductive argument. Every day in the history of the universe, the sun has risen. 18 00:01:50,610 --> 00:01:54,000 Tomorrow's another day. Tomorrow the sun will rise. 19 00:01:54,000 --> 00:02:00,750 Well, if it's really every day in the history of the universe, then that looks to be strong inductive argument. 20 00:02:00,750 --> 00:02:05,970 So in each of these arguments, the conclusion follows from the premises. 21 00:02:05,970 --> 00:02:13,020 But whereas these two premises raise the probability of that conclusion to a certain degree, 22 00:02:13,020 --> 00:02:18,690 these two premises raise the probability of that conclusion to a much greater degree. 23 00:02:18,690 --> 00:02:24,820 So inductive strength is a matter of degree, not either or. 24 00:02:24,820 --> 00:02:34,300 And even if the likelihood of the truth of the conclusion is significantly raised by the truth of the premises, it could still be false. 25 00:02:34,300 --> 00:02:38,740 Induction doesn't give a certainty as deduction does. 26 00:02:38,740 --> 00:02:48,310 So even if we look at this argument, which is inductively very strong indeed, we can see that that might be true and that might be true. 27 00:02:48,310 --> 00:02:56,890 Yet without that being true, possibly by tomorrow the sun will have blown up and it won't rise tomorrow. 28 00:02:56,890 --> 00:03:04,750 So the falsehood of the conclusion is consistent with the truth of the premises in an inductive argument, 29 00:03:04,750 --> 00:03:10,560 but not added up to a valid deductive argument. 30 00:03:10,560 --> 00:03:15,310 And that's because inductive reasoning depends on the principle of the uniformity of nature. 31 00:03:15,310 --> 00:03:26,230 The idea that the future will be like the past and this the idea that the future will be like the past, can't be justified without circularity. 32 00:03:26,230 --> 00:03:28,950 So if you say, well, well, you do always. 33 00:03:28,950 --> 00:03:34,420 And every time you put the kettle on in the morning, you're assuming that the future is going to be like the past. 34 00:03:34,420 --> 00:03:38,020 You're assuming that once again your kettle is going to boil. 35 00:03:38,020 --> 00:03:43,780 Well, maybe this is the time you'll get won't boil no matter how high you raise the temperature. 36 00:03:43,780 --> 00:03:50,680 Most unlikely, I think you'll agree. But why do you think the future is going to be like the past? 37 00:03:50,680 --> 00:03:54,790 Probable answer is because it's always been like the past in the past. 38 00:03:54,790 --> 00:04:04,240 But do you see that that that's a circular justification because you're using the past to justify claims about the future again. 39 00:04:04,240 --> 00:04:16,170 So any inductive argument is inductive because it rests on the principle of the uniformity of nature. 40 00:04:16,170 --> 00:04:24,720 Oops. Gone backwards and it's very important that it doesn't make induction inferior, that it doesn't give a certainty. 41 00:04:24,720 --> 00:04:31,020 Some people think that if deduction gives us certainty, an induction gives us only less than certainty. 42 00:04:31,020 --> 00:04:35,280 There's something inferior about induction. But that's not the case. 43 00:04:35,280 --> 00:04:45,240 It's just different. It's not inferior. And here's an inductive argument and a deductive argument just to see that. 44 00:04:45,240 --> 00:04:50,370 Do you see that this one's an inductive argument? So that's a white swan. 45 00:04:50,370 --> 00:04:53,730 You see a white swan, that's a white swan. You see another white swan. 46 00:04:53,730 --> 00:04:59,790 And then you think, well, actually, all the swans I've seen have been white, therefore all swans are white. 47 00:04:59,790 --> 00:05:09,750 So your inductively inferring a generalisation about all swans from all your observations of swans. 48 00:05:09,750 --> 00:05:15,000 And now here your deductively saying all swans are white. 49 00:05:15,000 --> 00:05:20,580 The creature in the next room is a swan. Therefore, the creature in the next room will be white. 50 00:05:20,580 --> 00:05:28,140 Do you see that's a deductive argument in that. If that's true and that's true, that must be true. 51 00:05:28,140 --> 00:05:34,320 But if that's true, that's true and that's true, that could still be false, couldn't it, 52 00:05:34,320 --> 00:05:43,980 because all swans you've observed doesn't actually necessarily cover all swans in the world or in the universe. 53 00:05:43,980 --> 00:05:48,900 So this one this argument rests on the principle of the uniformity of nature, 54 00:05:48,900 --> 00:05:56,880 the idea that if all the swans that you haven't seen are like the swans you have seen, then they'll all be white. 55 00:05:56,880 --> 00:06:04,320 But this one doesn't rest on the uniformity of nature, because here you're simply stating all swans are white. 56 00:06:04,320 --> 00:06:10,350 And if that's true and that's true, then that must be true. 57 00:06:10,350 --> 00:06:15,540 But of course, we've still got to say to yourself, well, how do you know that? 58 00:06:15,540 --> 00:06:25,930 And of course, well, how would we know that? What would be our justification for a claim like all swans are white, probably. 59 00:06:25,930 --> 00:06:32,940 It would be something like that, wouldn't it? So there's nothing inferior about induction, 60 00:06:32,940 --> 00:06:43,020 even though it doesn't give a certainty and we rely on induction almost everything we do, often successfully and without question. 61 00:06:43,020 --> 00:06:46,380 But in evaluating inductive arguments, 62 00:06:46,380 --> 00:06:55,110 we've got to use our judgement in a way that we don't have to use it with deduction because deduction is an either or matter. 63 00:06:55,110 --> 00:07:01,050 OK, well, there are different types of inductive arguments and have here of all types that are arguments from analogy, 64 00:07:01,050 --> 00:07:06,900 arguments from authority, inductive generalisations and causal generalisations. 65 00:07:06,900 --> 00:07:12,600 Let's have a look at all these here. This is an argument from analogy. 66 00:07:12,600 --> 00:07:17,160 So Jennifer liked my pen. This pen is similar to mine. 67 00:07:17,160 --> 00:07:24,120 Jennifer will like this pen. Can you see how that rests on the principle of the uniformity of nature? 68 00:07:24,120 --> 00:07:28,110 So Jennifer liked my pen. This similar pen is similar to my pen. 69 00:07:28,110 --> 00:07:35,970 Well, if Jennifer in the future likes the things she liked in the past, she should like this pen. 70 00:07:35,970 --> 00:07:43,170 So that's an argument from analogy and it's analogy because it rests on a similarity claim. 71 00:07:43,170 --> 00:07:48,810 Now, this one is the argument from authority. Einstein said that nothing goes faster than the speed of light. 72 00:07:48,810 --> 00:07:55,290 Einstein is an authority on physics. Therefore, nothing goes faster than the speed of light. 73 00:07:55,290 --> 00:08:04,560 Again, that rests on authority rather than analogy. And here's how to evaluate arguments from analogy. 74 00:08:04,560 --> 00:08:11,790 So if we have first thing we want to ask, as with any argument at all, whenever you're evaluating an argument, 75 00:08:11,790 --> 00:08:17,610 one of the first things you look for is, is the premise true or are the premises true? 76 00:08:17,610 --> 00:08:25,020 So if you're looking at this one, if these two premises are not true, then you've got no reason to believe the conclusion at all. 77 00:08:25,020 --> 00:08:31,710 If the premises are true, they raise the probability of the conclusion, though, as we know, it isn't certain. 78 00:08:31,710 --> 00:08:43,020 So first question to ask is, is the premise true? Second question to ask when evaluating an argument from analogy is, is there a similarity? 79 00:08:43,020 --> 00:08:46,620 So this pattern is similar to mine. Well, is that true? 80 00:08:46,620 --> 00:08:52,440 In what way is the pen similar to mine, the one that Jennifer liked before? 81 00:08:52,440 --> 00:09:04,770 And the next question is, is the similarity relevant? OK, well, maybe this pen is similar to mine in that they were both bought by Steve, let's say. 82 00:09:04,770 --> 00:09:09,090 Well, in that case, perhaps the similarity isn't relevant. 83 00:09:09,090 --> 00:09:12,420 It's there, but perhaps it isn't relevant because after all, 84 00:09:12,420 --> 00:09:18,570 if Jennifer liked the look of the pen, then the fact that it was bought by Steve is irrelevant. 85 00:09:18,570 --> 00:09:28,770 But if she liked the fact that the pen was red and this pen is similar because it's also red, then the similarity is relevant. 86 00:09:28,770 --> 00:09:40,680 And how strong is the similarity? The more alike this pen is to the pen that Jennifer liked, the more likely it is that Jennifer is going to like it. 87 00:09:40,680 --> 00:09:47,640 So I have a look at the strength of the similarity. The more points of similarity, the stronger the analogy. 88 00:09:47,640 --> 00:09:56,130 And are there any relevant analogies? So is there anything significantly different about my pen and this pen? 89 00:09:56,130 --> 00:10:06,800 If so, that might mean that the probability of the conclusion isn't raised very much, even if the premises are true. 90 00:10:06,800 --> 00:10:11,250 Okay, let's have a look at evaluating arguments from authority. 91 00:10:11,250 --> 00:10:16,360 So going back to this one, this is authority, the one about Einstein. 92 00:10:16,360 --> 00:10:25,380 Let's see what questions we've got to ask here. Firstly, again, is the premise true again and always we've got to ask, is the premise true? 93 00:10:25,380 --> 00:10:30,330 Second question we've got to ask is, is the person cited an expert in this area? 94 00:10:30,330 --> 00:10:38,520 Well, we're all prepared to accept that Einstein is an authority on physics, but that doesn't mean he's an authority on politics. 95 00:10:38,520 --> 00:10:45,840 So the fact that Einstein was a pacifist doesn't necessarily mean that pacifism is right. 96 00:10:45,840 --> 00:10:52,740 Even if we accept his authority on physics, we won't necessarily accept his authority elsewhere. 97 00:10:52,740 --> 00:10:58,380 So he's got to be not only an expert, but an expert in the particular area of the argument. 98 00:10:58,380 --> 00:11:09,210 The other thing we've got to ask is, is the expert biased? We might have an expert on television in an example using razorblades or something. 99 00:11:09,210 --> 00:11:13,740 There was a chap who was put forward as an expert, wasn't there? 100 00:11:13,740 --> 00:11:22,440 And you might ask, well, how much are they paying him to do this advertisement when he gives his recommendation 101 00:11:22,440 --> 00:11:27,990 for this particular product and it's an area in his area of expertise? 102 00:11:27,990 --> 00:11:31,710 Could he be biased? Could it be that we shouldn't listen to him? 103 00:11:31,710 --> 00:11:39,030 And finally, we might ask whether he's representative because physicists differ on a lot of things. 104 00:11:39,030 --> 00:11:44,430 Perhaps this expert is is an expert who holds a minority view. 105 00:11:44,430 --> 00:11:49,380 So whenever the BBC gets to get people together to talk about climate change, 106 00:11:49,380 --> 00:11:54,800 for example, you'll often have a scientist who speaks against climate change. 107 00:11:54,800 --> 00:12:02,570 Yes, he's an expert. He may or may not be biased, let's say he's not biased, but is he representative? 108 00:12:02,570 --> 00:12:09,500 Again, you've got to ask yourself, perhaps he's he's a dissenter on this particular opinion. 109 00:12:09,500 --> 00:12:15,290 And here's an inductive generalisation and on the other side, a causal generalisation. 110 00:12:15,290 --> 00:12:21,740 This is an inductive generalisation whenever I've tried to ring, but it's taken me hours to get through. 111 00:12:21,740 --> 00:12:25,550 Therefore, when I ring Beattie today, it'll take me hours to get through. 112 00:12:25,550 --> 00:12:32,660 So I'm inductively inferring from this premise to this conclusion perfectly reasonable. 113 00:12:32,660 --> 00:12:39,950 I think you'll agree this is a causal generalisation. Statistics say that married men live longer than single men. 114 00:12:39,950 --> 00:12:45,020 In other words, there's a correlation between being married and living longer between men who 115 00:12:45,020 --> 00:12:50,840 are married and therefore being married if male causes you to live longer. 116 00:12:50,840 --> 00:12:57,050 So here we're inferring from a correlation to a causal relationship. 117 00:12:57,050 --> 00:13:05,450 Let's have a look at how to evaluate these. So, again, first question always, is the premise true? 118 00:13:05,450 --> 00:13:13,190 Second question is how large is the sample? And let's say that whenever I've tried to ring Beattie, it's taken me hours to get through, 119 00:13:13,190 --> 00:13:23,780 but I've actually only tried twice and I just get very annoyed very, very easily and so on each on each of these two occasions. 120 00:13:23,780 --> 00:13:29,330 But I think you'll agree that the fewer the number of occasions on which I've tried to ring Beattie, 121 00:13:29,330 --> 00:13:36,590 the less credence we should attach to the conclusion of that argument. 122 00:13:36,590 --> 00:13:40,250 And we might also ask, is the sample typical? 123 00:13:40,250 --> 00:13:46,730 I mean, what I tried to ring Beattie at two o'clock in the morning, rather, at two o'clock in the afternoon. 124 00:13:46,730 --> 00:13:55,160 If I was, then maybe again, I shouldn't infer from that premise to that conclusion. 125 00:13:55,160 --> 00:14:02,720 And evaluating causal generalisations finally start off, of course, with is the premise true? 126 00:14:02,720 --> 00:14:13,610 A second question we ask is how strong is the correlation? OK, this correlation between men being married and men living a long time. 127 00:14:13,610 --> 00:14:23,240 But how I mean, is the correlation only about 60 percent of men who are married live longer or is it stronger than that? 128 00:14:23,240 --> 00:14:27,950 And the stronger the correlation, the better the argument here. 129 00:14:27,950 --> 00:14:33,590 Could the correlation be accidental? And sometimes correlations are accidental. 130 00:14:33,590 --> 00:14:39,410 When I was an undergraduate, we always talked about striking a match and a pineapple falling from a tree. 131 00:14:39,410 --> 00:14:44,570 You think? Well, even if there was a perfect correlation throughout the whole history of the 132 00:14:44,570 --> 00:14:50,570 universe between somebody striking a match and a pineapple falling from a tree, 133 00:14:50,570 --> 00:14:53,600 on the whole, you still think that correlation is accidental. 134 00:14:53,600 --> 00:15:02,180 You can't see how there would be a mechanism to underpin a causal relationship between those two types of events. 135 00:15:02,180 --> 00:15:05,600 You might also ask, could the causal relationship work the other way around? 136 00:15:05,600 --> 00:15:11,720 Could it be that men who live longer or sorry, men who are going to live longer get married? 137 00:15:11,720 --> 00:15:18,630 Perhaps there's something genetic that genetically inclines people to get married and also inclines them to live longer. 138 00:15:18,630 --> 00:15:26,570 That's the third one. So could the correlation be caused by a third thing that's attached that causes both the other two, 139 00:15:26,570 --> 00:15:31,160 which explains why the other two are correlated rather than that? 140 00:15:31,160 --> 00:15:34,880 There's, of course, the relation between those two. 141 00:15:34,880 --> 00:15:43,490 So, OK, they are that's induction and that's quickly for different inductive arguments and how to evaluate each of them. 142 00:15:43,490 --> 00:15:50,880 And there's the slide telling us a bit more about how to find out more.