1 00:00:00,750 --> 00:00:05,340 Welcome to the next Behney podcast, which this time is on arguments. 2 00:00:05,340 --> 00:00:10,590 Welcome to the people who are watching or listening to the podcast and welcome to everyone here. 3 00:00:10,590 --> 00:00:17,370 And philosophers study logic and logic tells us how to distinguish good arguments from bad. 4 00:00:17,370 --> 00:00:23,790 And there are many arguments, many problems that can be approached only by using logic. 5 00:00:23,790 --> 00:00:30,180 So consider the following sentence. Therapeutic cloning is morally acceptable. 6 00:00:30,180 --> 00:00:41,710 OK, just a reminder on what therapeutic cloning is. You can use the technology of cloning either for reproductive purposes where you produce it. 7 00:00:41,710 --> 00:00:46,560 So you take the nucleus from a human cell. 8 00:00:46,560 --> 00:00:49,680 You deem nucleate a cell from another animal, 9 00:00:49,680 --> 00:00:57,720 you put the nucleus into the cell and then you plant it into the uterus of a female of the species and let it grow to term. 10 00:00:57,720 --> 00:01:07,350 That would be reproductive cloning, therapeutic cloning. You would nucleate a cell, you would put the nucleus from the donor into that cell, 11 00:01:07,350 --> 00:01:18,720 and then you would use the resulting embryo for research or maybe to harvest stem cells from it again for use in research. 12 00:01:18,720 --> 00:01:24,210 So therapeutic cloning doesn't result in a live baby in this country. 13 00:01:24,210 --> 00:01:33,300 It is legal, but only under certain very stringent conditions. And the resulting embryo must be destroyed by the 14th day, whereas of course, 14 00:01:33,300 --> 00:01:37,650 for reproductive cloning, you hope that the embryo isn't destroyed at all. 15 00:01:37,650 --> 00:01:43,530 So we're looking at the sentence. Therapeutic cloning is morally acceptable. 16 00:01:43,530 --> 00:01:45,730 Some of us are going to believe that that's true. 17 00:01:45,730 --> 00:01:52,410 OK, some people think that that therapeutic cloning is going to lead to discovery of cures for all sorts of diseases. 18 00:01:52,410 --> 00:01:57,420 And for that reason, it's it's welcome and others or believe it's false. 19 00:01:57,420 --> 00:02:08,250 So some people think that therapeutic cloning involves the destruction of very early embryos and that for that reason, it's wrong. 20 00:02:08,250 --> 00:02:13,530 So there's a disagreement. Rational people disagree on this sentence. 21 00:02:13,530 --> 00:02:23,880 And there's no way that any empirical study, there's nothing we can do in the laboratory to determine whether that sentence is true or false. 22 00:02:23,880 --> 00:02:28,320 The only way we're going to determine whether it's true or false is by argument. 23 00:02:28,320 --> 00:02:37,320 And the reason there's nothing we can do in the laboratory is because science in the laboratory, you can't see how something ought to be. 24 00:02:37,320 --> 00:02:46,980 You can only see the way something is. So determining morality is not something we can do in the laboratory. 25 00:02:46,980 --> 00:02:56,590 We can do it only by argument. So, as I say, there are some sentences, the truth or falsehood of which can be determined only logically. 26 00:02:56,590 --> 00:03:05,250 And those of us who think that moral therapeutic cloning is morally acceptable and those of us who think it isn't can't both be right. 27 00:03:05,250 --> 00:03:13,590 I've just said that, haven't I? OK, so we can only decide that's the truth of that sentence by engaging in arguments. 28 00:03:13,590 --> 00:03:21,030 And when we construct an argument, we put forward a claim and one or more reasons for believing that claim. 29 00:03:21,030 --> 00:03:29,110 And the claim we put forward is called the conclusion and the reasons for believing the claim of called the premises. 30 00:03:29,110 --> 00:03:34,120 So here's an argument that at the moment isn't set out like an argument, 31 00:03:34,120 --> 00:03:40,510 we have a duty not to exploit non-human animals, but when we engineer their genes, this is what we're doing. 32 00:03:40,510 --> 00:03:50,530 Therefore, we shouldn't genetically engineer animals. And when we put out that argument in the way I suggested, here's the claim that's being made. 33 00:03:50,530 --> 00:03:57,880 We shouldn't genetically engineer non-human animals and here are the reasons that are being given for that claim. 34 00:03:57,880 --> 00:04:05,860 We have a duty not to exploit non-human animals and we exploit non-human animals when we use their genes. 35 00:04:05,860 --> 00:04:11,740 So first premise, second premise and the conclusion that's the claim being made. 36 00:04:11,740 --> 00:04:19,030 Those are the reasons being given for the claim. And when we set out an argument like this, we set it out. 37 00:04:19,030 --> 00:04:29,020 Logic books style makes the structure of the argument very easy to understand that there are different types of argument, 38 00:04:29,020 --> 00:04:36,040 but all of them fall into one of these two categories. They're either deductive arguments or they're inductive arguments. 39 00:04:36,040 --> 00:04:44,680 We're either engaging in deduction or in induction. So let's have a look at the differences here on this side. 40 00:04:44,680 --> 00:04:52,750 We've got a deductive argument. If the patient is in a permanent vegetative state, then he will not be conscious. 41 00:04:52,750 --> 00:04:58,570 The patient is in a permanent vegetative state. Therefore, the patient won't be conscious. 42 00:04:58,570 --> 00:05:07,870 OK, this is an inductive argument. People with Huntington's disease have always been observed to have the gene on chromosome four. 43 00:05:07,870 --> 00:05:15,250 Therefore, the next person who develops Huntington's disease will be observed to have the gene on chromosome four. 44 00:05:15,250 --> 00:05:19,690 Let's look at what the differences are between these two are. 45 00:05:19,690 --> 00:05:28,510 Deductive argument is such that if it's valid and its premises are true, then its conclusion must be true. 46 00:05:28,510 --> 00:05:34,090 And a deductive argument is either valid or invalid. It's an either or matter. 47 00:05:34,090 --> 00:05:43,570 So let's go back and have another look at this. OK, so if the patient is so if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. 48 00:05:43,570 --> 00:05:51,820 That's the sort. OK, is this true here? So if that's true and that's true, must that be true? 49 00:05:51,820 --> 00:05:58,450 I think you'll find that it does have to be. You can imagine all sorts of situations where that wouldn't be true and where that wouldn't be true. 50 00:05:58,450 --> 00:06:07,330 But we're not talking about those situations. We're talking about the situations where that is true and that is true and asking could that be false? 51 00:06:07,330 --> 00:06:12,220 And if it couldn't be, that's a deductively valid argument. 52 00:06:12,220 --> 00:06:16,090 OK, with induction, it isn't like that. 53 00:06:16,090 --> 00:06:24,880 OK, people with Huntington's disease have always in the past been observed to have the gene on chromosome four. 54 00:06:24,880 --> 00:06:34,030 Does that mean we will of certainty see that the gene on chromosome four of the next person with Huntington's disease? 55 00:06:34,030 --> 00:06:38,680 It seems hugely likely, but it's not absolutely certain. 56 00:06:38,680 --> 00:06:48,340 Is it just possibly there are different variants of Huntington's disease and one type won't have that as a characteristic. 57 00:06:48,340 --> 00:06:57,520 So where is the deductive argument is such that if the premise is true, the conclusion must be true with an inductive argument. 58 00:06:57,520 --> 00:07:04,900 The premise could be true without the conclusion being true, even if it's hugely likely that the premise is true. 59 00:07:04,900 --> 00:07:11,950 And again, with deduction, it's either or either the argument is valid or it isn't valid either. 60 00:07:11,950 --> 00:07:17,110 If these premises are true, this conclusion will be true or it isn't. 61 00:07:17,110 --> 00:07:21,130 The case will be looking at that in a bit more depth later on. 62 00:07:21,130 --> 00:07:25,000 Let's have another look at a bit more. 63 00:07:25,000 --> 00:07:35,470 So an inductively strong argument is such that if its premises are true, its conclusion is extremely likely to be true. 64 00:07:35,470 --> 00:07:42,250 OK, not certain to be true as it was with induction. Inductive arguments can be strong or weak. 65 00:07:42,250 --> 00:07:45,490 They're a matter of degree, whereas validity isn't. 66 00:07:45,490 --> 00:07:58,450 And again, let's go back and have a look at this so we see that if that's true, that may be hugely likely to be true, but it's not certain. 67 00:07:58,450 --> 00:08:06,220 Do you see that? And we can also see that that's a very strong inductive argument. 68 00:08:06,220 --> 00:08:10,030 And that's because we've got the word always in. 69 00:08:10,030 --> 00:08:15,610 People with Huntington's disease have always been observed to have the gene on chromosome four. 70 00:08:15,610 --> 00:08:21,910 Well, if it had been a few people have been observed to have that gene on chromosome 71 00:08:21,910 --> 00:08:27,260 four when they had Huntington's disease would be much less confident of that. 72 00:08:27,260 --> 00:08:33,580 And I'll show you in a minute another inductive argument where we wouldn't be confident at all. 73 00:08:33,580 --> 00:08:39,430 So inductive arguments, even at their strongest, do not deliver cast iron guarantees, 74 00:08:39,430 --> 00:08:47,050 all such arguments tacitly rely on what the philosopher Hume called the principle of the uniformity of nature. 75 00:08:47,050 --> 00:08:54,400 This belief underlies all our empirical, all our scientific reasoning, and it can't be justified without circularity. 76 00:08:54,400 --> 00:09:00,070 So imagine that we've seen the sun rise every single day in the history of the universe. 77 00:09:00,070 --> 00:09:04,120 That makes us fairly confident that it's going to rise again tomorrow. 78 00:09:04,120 --> 00:09:10,660 But of course, we could be in the position of Russell's chicken, who had seen the farmer coming out every single morning to feed it. 79 00:09:10,660 --> 00:09:17,500 So here a farmer comes this morning, used to be fed and instead you get your neck run because this is the morning, 80 00:09:17,500 --> 00:09:28,000 this is Christmas Day or something like that. And so just because the the in the past, the future has always been like the past, 81 00:09:28,000 --> 00:09:33,580 that doesn't justify us claiming that the future will be like the past in the future. 82 00:09:33,580 --> 00:09:40,870 If you're with me, we can't, without circularity, justify the claim that nature is uniform, 83 00:09:40,870 --> 00:09:45,970 because any claim that nature is uniform itself relies on the claim that nature is 84 00:09:45,970 --> 00:09:51,250 uniform and because induction relies on the principle of the uniformity of nature. 85 00:09:51,250 --> 00:10:01,630 That's why you don't get certainty. And I should point out that induction, the fact that induction doesn't give a certainty, doesn't make it inferior. 86 00:10:01,630 --> 00:10:09,910 Without induction, science would be impossible. And the whole of science assumes that the future will be like the past. 87 00:10:09,910 --> 00:10:14,110 If I can produce this result in my laboratory, 88 00:10:14,110 --> 00:10:21,160 then I expect you work in your laboratory and reproducing my experiment to come up with the same results. 89 00:10:21,160 --> 00:10:29,650 If you don't, then there's probably something wrong with my result because I expect my results to be replicable and so do you. 90 00:10:29,650 --> 00:10:33,610 And the examples I've offered so far have both been good arguments. 91 00:10:33,610 --> 00:10:39,670 One was a valid deductive argument. The other was an inductively strong inductive argument. 92 00:10:39,670 --> 00:10:47,410 But have a look at these arguments. If the patient is in a permanent vegetative state, then he will not be conscious. 93 00:10:47,410 --> 00:10:53,080 The patient is not conscious, therefore the patient is in a permanent vegetative state. 94 00:10:53,080 --> 00:11:01,080 What's wrong with that argument? We say, let's take a double that and the. 95 00:11:01,080 --> 00:11:08,720 It could be lots of reasons to be unconscious. Absolutely, we can provide many counterexamples to this. 96 00:11:08,720 --> 00:11:14,680 An account, for example, is a situation where the premises are both true and the conclusion false. 97 00:11:14,680 --> 00:11:23,590 And it could be true that if the patient is in a PVS, then he will not be conscious and true that the patient isn't conscious, 98 00:11:23,590 --> 00:11:28,840 but that many situations in which she's not MBBS, he's unconscious for some other reason, 99 00:11:28,840 --> 00:11:32,980 maybe just fell off the stage and knocked himself unconscious or whatever. 100 00:11:32,980 --> 00:11:41,500 So we can give lots of counterexamples to this. And therefore, that's a bad deductive argument is invalid. 101 00:11:41,500 --> 00:11:48,130 It's not the case that there's no sorry there is a possible situation which the premise is true and the conclusion false, 102 00:11:48,130 --> 00:11:53,680 and therefore the argument is invalid. And here's a bad inductive argument. 103 00:11:53,680 --> 00:12:01,540 When I passed that exam, I wore my red shirt. Therefore, if I wear my red shirt next time I take an example, pass that exam to. 104 00:12:01,540 --> 00:12:07,240 Now we all think like this. Actually, we do. The thing about human beings is we can't not think like that. 105 00:12:07,240 --> 00:12:13,960 If we do something and it's successful, the probability of doing it again is hugely raised. 106 00:12:13,960 --> 00:12:21,070 So if this is the situation, if and if it's the red shirt that seems salient to us, that's what will we'll do again. 107 00:12:21,070 --> 00:12:29,140 And even if we laugh at ourselves as we do it, we might still do it. But actually, that's a very poor argument, isn't it? 108 00:12:29,140 --> 00:12:36,190 Because actually this gives us hardly raises the likelihood of our passing the exam at all. 109 00:12:36,190 --> 00:12:50,570 So that's an inductively weak arguments. You see, again, that validity is a matter of either or, whereas induction is a matter of degree. 110 00:12:50,570 --> 00:12:55,940 I've just said that so we can skip on no, sorry, I said again. 111 00:12:55,940 --> 00:13:02,300 OK, the argument on the on the right is an inductively weak argument. 112 00:13:02,300 --> 00:13:09,020 Sorry, who started the argument on the left? That one is an invalid argument. 113 00:13:09,020 --> 00:13:18,220 The premise of the argument, even if they are true, give us no reason to believe the conclusion, ok? 114 00:13:18,220 --> 00:13:24,370 And then if we look at the one on the right, it's an inductively weak argument, 115 00:13:24,370 --> 00:13:29,980 even if the premise is true, the likelihood of the conclusion is hardly raised at all. 116 00:13:29,980 --> 00:13:36,850 So even if we're certain of the truth of the premise, this gives us very little reason to believe the truth of the conclusion. 117 00:13:36,850 --> 00:13:43,930 That's the argument on the right. A bad argument like the two we've just looked at tells us nothing. 118 00:13:43,930 --> 00:13:49,210 But if we don't recognise it as bad, it can easily leave us astray. 119 00:13:49,210 --> 00:13:52,510 Can you see that? Certainly. The argument on the left there, 120 00:13:52,510 --> 00:14:01,600 many people would miss the fact that actually what you're doing there is affirming the consequent rather than arguing validly. 121 00:14:01,600 --> 00:14:06,820 And if we don't recognise bad arguments as bad, it will lead astray. 122 00:14:06,820 --> 00:14:13,090 So what we want to do is learn how to evaluate arguments properly and in evaluation argument. 123 00:14:13,090 --> 00:14:18,310 There are two questions that we've got to ask. The first is, are the premises all true? 124 00:14:18,310 --> 00:14:24,340 And the reason for this rather complicated syntax here is some arguments have only one premise. 125 00:14:24,340 --> 00:14:29,330 There's no reason to think that an argument needed to have two premises or more than two. 126 00:14:29,330 --> 00:14:36,970 And so is its premise. True is one question was asked. And the second question is, does the conclusion follow from the premises? 127 00:14:36,970 --> 00:14:45,190 So whenever you're asking yourself whether an argument is a good argument or a bad argument, these are the two questions that must be asked. 128 00:14:45,190 --> 00:14:52,720 Are the premises true? Does the conclusion follow? Those are the two key questions. 129 00:14:52,720 --> 00:14:58,210 And looking at these, this is a very complicated slide and maybe I should have broken it up a bit. 130 00:14:58,210 --> 00:15:03,670 But looking at the two questions, there are four possible answers to these questions taken together. 131 00:15:03,670 --> 00:15:07,240 And it might be that the answer to both questions is yes. 132 00:15:07,240 --> 00:15:11,710 Yes, the premises are true. And yes, the conclusion does follow. 133 00:15:11,710 --> 00:15:16,750 And so the premises are all true. The conclusion follows in this situation, 134 00:15:16,750 --> 00:15:24,820 the argument is said to be sound and the sound argument is exactly one where the premises are true and the conclusion follows. 135 00:15:24,820 --> 00:15:31,150 A sound argument gives us excellent reason to believe the conclusion. It's very definitely a good argument. 136 00:15:31,150 --> 00:15:36,640 OK, so if the answer to both questions is yes, yes, you've got a good argument. 137 00:15:36,640 --> 00:15:41,560 If the answer to the first question is yes, but the answer to the second is no, 138 00:15:41,560 --> 00:15:49,000 then you've got an argument which is such that although it's all its premises are true, the conclusion doesn't follow from them. 139 00:15:49,000 --> 00:15:55,660 And in this situation, the truth of the premises gives you no reason at all to believe in the truth of the conclusion. 140 00:15:55,660 --> 00:16:02,890 The premises and the conclusion are not related in the right way to convince us of anything. 141 00:16:02,890 --> 00:16:08,560 And so imagine, for example, that the premises of arguments three and four are true. 142 00:16:08,560 --> 00:16:13,180 So the last two arguments we had, even if the premises are true, 143 00:16:13,180 --> 00:16:22,810 they don't give us any reason to believe the conclusion because the conclusion doesn't follow and those arguments can't be considered good at all. 144 00:16:22,810 --> 00:16:32,300 The third possibility is that the answer to one is no, the premises aren't true, but the answer to two is yes, the conclusion follows. 145 00:16:32,300 --> 00:16:36,610 OK, so the premises provide good reason to believe the conclusion. 146 00:16:36,610 --> 00:16:40,990 The conclusion follows from the premises, but the premises aren't true. 147 00:16:40,990 --> 00:16:48,130 So this argument is such that although its conclusion follows from its premises, at least one of the premises is false. 148 00:16:48,130 --> 00:16:58,240 In this situation. The fact that a premise is false means we haven't got reason to believe the conclusion despite its following from the premises. 149 00:16:58,240 --> 00:17:06,550 But the fact that the conclusion follows from the premise means that the argument can be considered a good argument. 150 00:17:06,550 --> 00:17:14,440 By that we mean as an argument, it's good and as we often don't know whether a premise is true or false or not. 151 00:17:14,440 --> 00:17:18,130 Actually, as logicians, that's what we're concerned about. 152 00:17:18,130 --> 00:17:26,470 What we're looking for is good arguments. We're looking for whether a conclusion follows from a premise rather than whether the premises are true. 153 00:17:26,470 --> 00:17:35,320 So we call that a good argument, which is distinct from a sound argument, which is a good argument with true premises. 154 00:17:35,320 --> 00:17:45,220 And finally, we might hit the situation where the answer to both questions is no, it hasn't got true premises and its conclusion doesn't follow. 155 00:17:45,220 --> 00:17:49,000 Well, what do we think about this argument? We think it should go in the bin. 156 00:17:49,000 --> 00:17:56,350 It's a useless argument. It shouldn't convince you of anything. So two questions you should ask always. 157 00:17:56,350 --> 00:18:00,850 Whatever your argument you're looking at, those are is premises true? 158 00:18:00,850 --> 00:18:03,500 Does the conclusion follow from the premises? 159 00:18:03,500 --> 00:18:13,150 There are four different possibilities if you ask those two questions, and those are the ramifications of the answers in each case. 160 00:18:13,150 --> 00:18:17,770 And I'd just like to point out that the relation of following from covers to. 161 00:18:17,770 --> 00:18:26,680 Different sorts of relation between a set of premises and a conclusion, so the conclusion of a deductive argument follows from its premises. 162 00:18:26,680 --> 00:18:35,440 If the argument is valid and the conclusion of an inductive argument follows from its premises, if the argument is inductively strong. 163 00:18:35,440 --> 00:18:43,540 So there are two different meanings for follows from depending on whether you're looking at a deductive argument or an inductive one. 164 00:18:43,540 --> 00:18:48,730 And we're going to look at the difference between those two in the next podcast. 165 00:18:48,730 --> 00:18:55,690 So in this podcast, we've considered what the two sorts of follows from have in common the fact that an 166 00:18:55,690 --> 00:19:04,170 argument could get counted as a good argument only when it's valid or inductively strong. 167 00:19:04,170 --> 00:19:09,060 And if you'd like to know more, here's the list of places you might go. 168 00:19:09,060 --> 00:19:13,680 Thank you.