1 00:00:02,040 --> 00:00:08,940 Well, welcome everybody to the first lecture on Alan Turing on computer ability and intelligence. 2 00:00:08,940 --> 00:00:18,960 I'm Peter Milliken. As you see at Harvard College and as most of you probably know, I'm quite keen on computer science and philosophy, 3 00:00:18,960 --> 00:00:23,280 which is the degree programme towards which these lectures around. 4 00:00:23,280 --> 00:00:28,260 Anyone here who's not doing computer science philosophy? You're very welcome to. 5 00:00:28,260 --> 00:00:33,300 It's a very interesting topic, and I hope you enjoy the lectures. 6 00:00:33,300 --> 00:00:41,250 As you'll be aware, they're being recorded this year. That's so that they're available in the future. 7 00:00:41,250 --> 00:00:45,760 So for that reason, I'm not going to be taking any questions during the lectures. 8 00:00:45,760 --> 00:00:52,680 But if any problems arise, I will be organising classes during the term for anyone who needs them. 9 00:00:52,680 --> 00:01:01,200 Okay, those doing computer science philosophy later in the term will be having tutorials on the stuff to do with philosophy of mind. 10 00:01:01,200 --> 00:01:07,670 And so when you'll be writing essays and I'll give you details about that later. 11 00:01:07,670 --> 00:01:15,200 The role of the course is part of the introduction to philosophy for the prelims course in computer science and philosophy. 12 00:01:15,200 --> 00:01:24,740 And just to get this out of the way, you have a three hour examination and it contains six either all questions on general 13 00:01:24,740 --> 00:01:32,780 philosophy and six questions on curing from which you are expected to choose for. 14 00:01:32,780 --> 00:01:38,300 And you have to do at least one from each section, so you could end up doing one question on curing. 15 00:01:38,300 --> 00:01:49,310 You could end up doing three. In practise, I have to say computer science philosophy students tend to do more Turing papers than gentle questions, 16 00:01:49,310 --> 00:01:54,590 so you'll probably find that the course is quite fruitful from that point of view. 17 00:01:54,590 --> 00:02:04,970 Here's the overall plan of the lectures. Today we'll be talking about types of number about cantor infinities diagonal argument. 18 00:02:04,970 --> 00:02:09,890 Next lecture We're going to be talking about Hilbert programme and girdles theorem. 19 00:02:09,890 --> 00:02:16,310 We won't be going through Girdles Theorem in all detail, but we will be seeing how it works. 20 00:02:16,310 --> 00:02:23,030 The ingenious method by which girdle proved his result, and by then, you'll understand why it's important. 21 00:02:23,030 --> 00:02:29,390 Lecture three to five Focus on the the really main core of the lectures, 22 00:02:29,390 --> 00:02:38,540 which is Alan Turing's 1936 paper on computable numbers with an application to the incidence problem. 23 00:02:38,540 --> 00:02:45,890 Now that was the paper that introduced the Turing machine and hence virtually invented the computer. 24 00:02:45,890 --> 00:02:50,690 We have a set text for that, which makes it feasible to do this. 25 00:02:50,690 --> 00:02:58,790 It's a fiercely difficult paper, but with the help of this book by Charles Petzold, you should, I hope, find it entirely manageable. 26 00:02:58,790 --> 00:03:04,490 Those doing computer science and philosophy, it's probably a good idea to buy this book. 27 00:03:04,490 --> 00:03:11,360 The reason is that you might very well find as you go through it, that you want to make notes and highlights and so forth on it. 28 00:03:11,360 --> 00:03:17,630 And of course, you shouldn't be doing that with library books. Okay, so that's lecture three to five. 29 00:03:17,630 --> 00:03:23,240 And then in the last three lectures, we'll be looking at Alan Turing's other very famous paper, 30 00:03:23,240 --> 00:03:30,830 the 1950 paper computing machinery and intelligence, and that's the paper that introduced the Turing test. 31 00:03:30,830 --> 00:03:35,810 So that's where we get into stuff from philosophy of mind and so on. 32 00:03:35,810 --> 00:03:39,860 Okay, so I've mentioned the textbook. Here are the details about it. 33 00:03:39,860 --> 00:03:47,420 It really does contain everything you need to know on the background of the 1936 paper that it contains the 34 00:03:47,420 --> 00:03:57,050 actual text of the paper if you see highlighted here in grey so that you can see exactly what Turing wrote. 35 00:03:57,050 --> 00:04:05,720 But it's surrounded by a lot of commentary, which makes it all comprehensible, explains difficulties, explains corrections and so forth. 36 00:04:05,720 --> 00:04:15,560 What I'll be doing in these lectures is giving you, I hope, enough material that will make that paper much more comprehensible. 37 00:04:15,560 --> 00:04:22,010 Even with petzold help, you might find it difficult sometimes to see the wood for the trees in the lectures. 38 00:04:22,010 --> 00:04:28,670 I'm going to be focussing on bits that are particularly difficult and setting the background for that. 39 00:04:28,670 --> 00:04:35,420 OK? Highly recommended reading a couple of books by Andrew Hodges, which are biographical books about Turing, 40 00:04:35,420 --> 00:04:41,300 but obviously also contain quite a lot of stuff that's relevant to what we're going to be talking about. 41 00:04:41,300 --> 00:04:47,510 His mammoth biography from 1983 and very well known. 42 00:04:47,510 --> 00:04:52,970 If you want to read something during the long vacation, maybe that's a good idea. 43 00:04:52,970 --> 00:05:02,180 A much shorter book, just 58 pages is very well worth reading to get a feel for what Turing was about, 44 00:05:02,180 --> 00:05:09,710 and I'll be mentioning this book, which is a huge collection on Turing remarkable value. 45 00:05:09,710 --> 00:05:14,690 It's actually surprisingly cheap for a book of over 900 pages. 46 00:05:14,690 --> 00:05:21,740 So if you're a real enthusiast and you want an absolute doorstop of a book, that's worth considering that you should. 47 00:05:21,740 --> 00:05:30,560 Most of you have it in college libraries. And if you don't get them to order it and this small book, it's a classic book on girdles proof. 48 00:05:30,560 --> 00:05:36,530 I'll be mentioning next lecture. Okay, so who was Alan Turing? 49 00:05:36,530 --> 00:05:43,220 Well, he was born in 1912, educated at Hazelhurst and Sherburne schools. 50 00:05:43,220 --> 00:05:49,400 His parents were in India, so he was at boarding school. 51 00:05:49,400 --> 00:05:53,960 He formed a close relationship with another lad at the school called Christopher Malcolm. 52 00:05:53,960 --> 00:05:59,030 And both of them applied to read maths at Trinity Cambridge. 53 00:05:59,030 --> 00:06:06,230 Malcolm was accepted. Turing wasn't. But the next year, Malcolm died of tuberculosis. 54 00:06:06,230 --> 00:06:11,810 And it seems they had a very intimate affair. Alan Turing was gay, 55 00:06:11,810 --> 00:06:23,630 losing his intimate friend had a profound effect on him and got him thinking a lot seems about the nature of mind where the mind can survive death, 56 00:06:23,630 --> 00:06:26,370 the relation between mind and body and so forth. 57 00:06:26,370 --> 00:06:36,710 I mean, so some of this is speculative, but it seems very plausible later in his life, as is well known. 58 00:06:36,710 --> 00:06:41,060 He played a huge role in the war in the Second World War. 59 00:06:41,060 --> 00:06:48,920 He was largely responsible for the techniques by which the Nazi Enigma codes were decrypted, 60 00:06:48,920 --> 00:06:56,360 thus enabling allied shipping to escape the U-boats in the Atlantic without cheering. 61 00:06:56,360 --> 00:07:01,100 It's entirely possible that the war would have gone on a lot longer and been a lot more 62 00:07:01,100 --> 00:07:07,670 difficult to win because without being able to divert the ships around the U-boat packs, 63 00:07:07,670 --> 00:07:14,000 Britain's position would really have been quite perilous in the early 1940s. 64 00:07:14,000 --> 00:07:19,130 This was completely unknown until relatively recently because it was all official secrets, 65 00:07:19,130 --> 00:07:25,880 and Turing was prosecuted for homosexuality in the early 1950s. 66 00:07:25,880 --> 00:07:29,840 And again, nobody knew what a hero he was. 67 00:07:29,840 --> 00:07:41,960 He was forced to take hormone treatment, which had very bad effects on him, and he ended up probably committing suicide in 1954. 68 00:07:41,960 --> 00:07:45,170 He seems to have set it up in such a way that there was a little bit of ambiguity. 69 00:07:45,170 --> 00:07:53,180 He he apparently took a bite out of an apple on which he'd committed suicide cyanide. 70 00:07:53,180 --> 00:07:57,410 But it is possible that he killed himself by mistake. 71 00:07:57,410 --> 00:08:02,960 So a plausible suggestion is that he deliberately set it up that way so that his 72 00:08:02,960 --> 00:08:08,030 mother would be able to believe that he hadn't actually killed himself deliberately. 73 00:08:08,030 --> 00:08:11,810 Anyway, back to his early life, he reapplied to Cambridge. 74 00:08:11,810 --> 00:08:17,450 In 1930, he was accepted for King's College, went up in 1931. 75 00:08:17,450 --> 00:08:25,340 He took his part to try pass exams in 1934, passed with distinction and got a research student ship. 76 00:08:25,340 --> 00:08:33,920 Then the next year, he was elected to a three year fellowship, so he obviously did extremely well in maths at Cambridge. 77 00:08:33,920 --> 00:08:43,010 By 1935, he was a fellow and he attended a Part three course given by Max Neumann on the foundations of mathematics. 78 00:08:43,010 --> 00:08:49,550 And this, again, is something that seems to have had quite a profound effect on him to understand why we 79 00:08:49,550 --> 00:08:54,560 need to look a bit at one of the greatest mathematicians of the early 20th century. 80 00:08:54,560 --> 00:09:05,420 David Hilbert Hilbert was born in Konigsberg, the city with which Immanuel Kant is greatly associated. 81 00:09:05,420 --> 00:09:12,320 He was perhaps the most influential mathematician of the early 20th century, partly because he set the agenda. 82 00:09:12,320 --> 00:09:18,200 He made a point of saying, Here are big problems on which we should focus. 83 00:09:18,200 --> 00:09:25,880 He also developed the formalised approach to philosophy of maths. So those of you who study philosophy of maths you will come across, you know, 84 00:09:25,880 --> 00:09:31,550 the the politeness, the approach, the intuition is the approach, the formalist approach. 85 00:09:31,550 --> 00:09:43,730 And Hilbert is very much a founder of the last of these, the formalised approach CS mathematics as involving manipulations of symbols. 86 00:09:43,730 --> 00:09:50,870 So we discuss proofs and things in terms of their syntactic properties, and we'll see that playing a role later, 87 00:09:50,870 --> 00:09:59,540 especially next time at the 19:00 Paris International Conference of Congress of Mathematicians. 88 00:09:59,540 --> 00:10:07,320 He famously listed prominent unsolved problems of mathematics, including this one, 89 00:10:07,320 --> 00:10:13,430 the tenth problem determination of the solve ability of a Die-Off and time equation. 90 00:10:13,430 --> 00:10:17,660 Now I put this in, partly because Petzold, in his book, 91 00:10:17,660 --> 00:10:24,800 discusses these at some length and very interestingly, so I recommend that you go and look at his book. 92 00:10:24,800 --> 00:10:39,170 The question is, suppose you have an equation which has a number of unknowns and with integer coefficients, can there be a solution to that equation? 93 00:10:39,170 --> 00:10:50,510 And trying to devise a process by which you can tell whether there is a solution or not is a major problem. 94 00:10:50,510 --> 00:10:56,630 The the equations were named after an Alexandrian mathematician, Dave Fanta. 95 00:10:56,630 --> 00:11:05,590 The most famous example of a die Fantine equation is associated with them as last Theorem X to the end, plus Y to the end. 96 00:11:05,590 --> 00:11:12,880 And does this have any integer solutions when N is greater than two? 97 00:11:12,880 --> 00:11:17,350 I mean, it clearly does when any equals one. 98 00:11:17,350 --> 00:11:23,560 It clearly does. When any calls to, for example, three squared plus four squared equals five squared. 99 00:11:23,560 --> 00:11:27,820 Does it have any when an equal three or four or more than that? 100 00:11:27,820 --> 00:11:33,040 And for many years, this was a huge puzzle. 101 00:11:33,040 --> 00:11:44,770 The great French mathematician Thelma famously wrote in the margin of one of his notebooks that he had discovered a wonderful proof of this theorem, 102 00:11:44,770 --> 00:11:52,870 but I don't have room to write it down in the margin. And this intrigued future generations of mathematicians. 103 00:11:52,870 --> 00:12:00,550 They all tried to discover or rediscover this proof that Thelma had supposedly discovered. 104 00:12:00,550 --> 00:12:11,320 It actually took a huge amount of work by lots of mathematicians and eventually was proved by Andrew Wiles in 1995. 105 00:12:11,320 --> 00:12:19,000 I think most people think that Sam probably found an ingenious proof that applied to certain cases, 106 00:12:19,000 --> 00:12:30,920 but not to all because proving it as a general theorem is actually extraordinarily difficult requires very sophisticated mathematics. 107 00:12:30,920 --> 00:12:36,920 OK, let's have a quick look at some of Gilbert's other problems, apart from the one concerning Di Fantine equations. 108 00:12:36,920 --> 00:12:44,420 We've got the continuum hypothesis that's a very important problem in philosophy of mathematics. 109 00:12:44,420 --> 00:12:49,040 Again, here on, I'm not going to discuss it, but I'm just going to refer you to Petzold. 110 00:12:49,040 --> 00:12:53,660 That's something he discusses and is well worth knowing about proving the 111 00:12:53,660 --> 00:12:59,630 consistency of the axioms of arithmetic that something will be coming back to, 112 00:12:59,630 --> 00:13:10,310 particularly next time. The Riemann hypothesis and Goldmark conjecture gold, but conjecture is a favourite of philosophers. 113 00:13:10,310 --> 00:13:23,090 It's the claim that any even number greater than two can be expressed as the sum of two prime numbers. 114 00:13:23,090 --> 00:13:29,450 Philosophers love it because it hasn't yet been proved. 115 00:13:29,450 --> 00:13:39,860 So when I started out studying maths at Oxford quite a long time ago, there were three of these very famous unsolved problems, 116 00:13:39,860 --> 00:13:44,360 and one of them was the full-color theorem, which got proved the subsequent year. 117 00:13:44,360 --> 00:13:49,160 One of them was Fermat's Last Theorem, which, as I say, was proved in 1995. 118 00:13:49,160 --> 00:13:54,620 I'm hoping that Girlboss conjecture will last a bit longer so that we philosophers can continue to give. 119 00:13:54,620 --> 00:13:59,220 It is a nice example. OK. 120 00:13:59,220 --> 00:14:09,030 Let's come to here. But the challenge is that Hilbert set, he set out a programme in philosophy of mathematics. 121 00:14:09,030 --> 00:14:15,390 He wanted to establish foundations for mathematics, which were provably consistent. 122 00:14:15,390 --> 00:14:24,660 So starting from axioms which were ideally self-evident, clearly true and manifestly consistent. 123 00:14:24,660 --> 00:14:32,730 So even if you can't necessarily see immediately that they're all true, you want to be able to prove that they all hang together. 124 00:14:32,730 --> 00:14:37,410 There's no inconsistency there and a set of axioms from which in principle, 125 00:14:37,410 --> 00:14:43,440 all mathematical truths can be deduced by the standard rules of First Order predicate logic. 126 00:14:43,440 --> 00:14:51,960 So I assume you've all learnt, first of all, the predicate logic, standard logic that we inherited from Fraga. 127 00:14:51,960 --> 00:15:06,300 Is it possible to get a set of basic axioms from which by those rules, you can deduce all of mathematics or at least all of arithmetic? 128 00:15:06,300 --> 00:15:09,930 A related problem, the incidents problem, 129 00:15:09,930 --> 00:15:17,130 the problem that Alan Turing was going to be concerned with the decision problem, can an effective procedure be devised, 130 00:15:17,130 --> 00:15:26,310 which would demonstrate in a finite time with any given mathematical proposition is or is not provable from a given set of axioms? 131 00:15:26,310 --> 00:15:36,930 OK, so we want these axioms. We want them to be provably consistent and complete, such that all of mathematics can be deduced from them. 132 00:15:36,930 --> 00:15:42,690 We also want to have a procedure which in a finite time is going to tell us as it were, 133 00:15:42,690 --> 00:15:48,240 mechanically simply by applying this procedure in a mechanical way to tell us 134 00:15:48,240 --> 00:15:53,950 whether any given proposition is or is not provable from the set of axioms. 135 00:15:53,950 --> 00:16:03,180 Okay. Some of the relations between those will become much clearer next time when we talk about girdle. 136 00:16:03,180 --> 00:16:11,070 The 1936 paper, which is said, the sort of central topic of these lectures. 137 00:16:11,070 --> 00:16:15,570 Second, the decision problem, the entitlements problem. 138 00:16:15,570 --> 00:16:20,370 It showed, in fact, that there could be no such procedure. 139 00:16:20,370 --> 00:16:26,490 But the paper starts, as the title suggests, from the concept of a computable number. 140 00:16:26,490 --> 00:16:33,990 So then the paper the ultimate aim of Turing's paper is to settle the incidence problem. 141 00:16:33,990 --> 00:16:39,510 It gets there by talking about a certain kind of number, a computable number. 142 00:16:39,510 --> 00:16:48,900 Now, in order to understand what those are and how they fit in with everything else, we're going to need to talk first about types of number. 143 00:16:48,900 --> 00:16:54,990 So that's actually going to be the main focus of the rest of this lecture. In the next lecture, as I've said, we'll move on to girdle. 144 00:16:54,990 --> 00:16:57,390 We'll talk about completeness and consistency. 145 00:16:57,390 --> 00:17:08,700 And then by the third lecture, we'll have a good framework for understanding where Turing's paper comes in and and why it takes the form it does. 146 00:17:08,700 --> 00:17:18,240 Okay, so what we we're going to look at various types of number and find interesting results about some of these sets of numbers. 147 00:17:18,240 --> 00:17:25,530 So here are some set standards used in mathematics the set of natural numbers one two three four You're studying computer science. 148 00:17:25,530 --> 00:17:32,310 You've probably been told the first natural number zero. I'm going to take the first natural number to be one because zero. 149 00:17:32,310 --> 00:17:37,770 Isn't that natural? Is it real? OK? It's actually pretty harmless for most contexts. 150 00:17:37,770 --> 00:17:41,520 Whether you take the natural numbers are starting from zero or one. 151 00:17:41,520 --> 00:17:52,350 We're going to go with one the set of integers from Xylem and German of the symbol Zaidi's commonly used for that. 152 00:17:52,350 --> 00:17:59,130 The set of integers obviously is both positive and negative, and zero the set of rational numbers. 153 00:17:59,130 --> 00:18:05,880 A rational number is simply a fraction of integers, so you've got an integer on the top, you've got an integer on the bottom. 154 00:18:05,880 --> 00:18:15,690 Obviously not zero on the bottom. And that set is commonly denominated Q, probably for quotient. 155 00:18:15,690 --> 00:18:25,320 And then there are real numbers, say R, and real numbers essentially correspond to to all the non complex numbers, 156 00:18:25,320 --> 00:18:32,160 all the numbers that we normally handle when we're doing things like calculus or trigonometry and so forth. 157 00:18:32,160 --> 00:18:41,370 Those are all real numbers now. Real numbers include irrational numbers, numbers that cannot be written as a fraction of integers, 158 00:18:41,370 --> 00:18:48,100 algebraic numbers which are roots of algebraic equations and transmittal numbers, which on either of those? 159 00:18:48,100 --> 00:18:55,350 OK, I'll be coming to those a little bit later in the lecture. We're not going to be talking here about the set of complex numbers. 160 00:18:55,350 --> 00:19:02,920 Some of what we do could apply equally to complex numbers, but they're not really relevant to the business here. 161 00:19:02,920 --> 00:19:09,010 OK. Now, these are obviously all infinite sets. 162 00:19:09,010 --> 00:19:17,980 There's an infinite number of natural numbers. There's an infinite number of rational numbers and so forth. 163 00:19:17,980 --> 00:19:24,820 But what Georg Cantor did was show that not all of these infinities are the same. 164 00:19:24,820 --> 00:19:29,710 We're going to end up with more than one type of infinity. 165 00:19:29,710 --> 00:19:35,200 So that's the theory of Tehran's finite cardinal numbers. 166 00:19:35,200 --> 00:19:46,150 And the key to understanding how this works is a principle that's to my mind, somewhat ironically known as Hume's principle. 167 00:19:46,150 --> 00:19:56,440 As you probably know, I'm rather a fan of David Hume, but it has to be said that philosophy of mathematics wasn't exactly Hume's strongest point. 168 00:19:56,440 --> 00:20:02,740 So there's an irony in this absolute key principle in the philosophy of mathematics being named after him. 169 00:20:02,740 --> 00:20:13,630 But the reason is that Fraga, in foundations of arithmetic, pointed out that Hume had enunciated this principle when two numbers are so combined, 170 00:20:13,630 --> 00:20:20,770 as the one has always a unit answering to every use of the other, we pronounce them equal. 171 00:20:20,770 --> 00:20:25,570 OK, so let's see what's being said here. 172 00:20:25,570 --> 00:20:34,930 The idea is that if you have two sets of objects and you can put those two sets in one to one 173 00:20:34,930 --> 00:20:44,350 correspondence so that each unit in one of the sets corresponds to one and only one unit in the other set, 174 00:20:44,350 --> 00:20:48,220 then you can say that the two sets are equally numerous. 175 00:20:48,220 --> 00:20:52,150 They have the same number of elements. 176 00:20:52,150 --> 00:20:59,670 Mathematically, we well, first of all, we use a technical term called finality for the number of elements in a set. 177 00:20:59,670 --> 00:21:07,660 And this is meant to be a generalisation so that we can extend it to infinite numbers, not just finite. 178 00:21:07,660 --> 00:21:17,290 So two sets of the same card inanity if and only if Abhijit two function were a one to one, correspondence can be defined between them. 179 00:21:17,290 --> 00:21:25,800 So let's just get clear what objective function is a function that is both injected and surge active. 180 00:21:25,800 --> 00:21:29,230 So and this is an example of an injected function here. 181 00:21:29,230 --> 00:21:40,540 We've got the domain here, we've got the code domain and you can see that this object is the function of this. 182 00:21:40,540 --> 00:21:44,470 This is the function of this or, as we say, the image of it. 183 00:21:44,470 --> 00:21:54,760 And you can see that there is no object in the code domain, which is the image of two or more objects in the domain. 184 00:21:54,760 --> 00:21:58,630 You never get two arrows going to the same point. OK. 185 00:21:58,630 --> 00:22:04,510 That's an injected function. Here's an example of a subjective function. 186 00:22:04,510 --> 00:22:11,140 Here you can see this one is not injected. We sometimes do have two arrows going at the same point. 187 00:22:11,140 --> 00:22:17,710 But there is no object within the code domain, which is not hit by at least one arrow. 188 00:22:17,710 --> 00:22:34,060 Got that? Now, do you agree that if we have an injected function, if not, we never have two arrows going to the same point here, 189 00:22:34,060 --> 00:22:39,730 then this set must have at least as many elements as this one. 190 00:22:39,730 --> 00:22:45,780 Yeah. Because there has to be a separate element for every act. 191 00:22:45,780 --> 00:22:53,550 Whereas if we have a subjective function, that means every element here gets hit by at least one arrow, 192 00:22:53,550 --> 00:22:59,850 then this set must have at least as many elements as that one agree. 193 00:22:59,850 --> 00:23:06,930 So if we have objective function, a function that is both injected and surgically, if a one to one correspondence, 194 00:23:06,930 --> 00:23:11,700 it follows that the two sets must have the same commonality, the same number of elements. 195 00:23:11,700 --> 00:23:20,940 Now, essentially, what we do when we talk about infinite sets is we take that principle, which is so natural with finite sets, 196 00:23:20,940 --> 00:23:30,300 and we extend it and apply it to infinite sets and cantors were basically comes from doing that. 197 00:23:30,300 --> 00:23:37,260 OK, now when we're dealing with infinite sets rather than attempting to define objection, 198 00:23:37,260 --> 00:23:48,300 we normally make do with a search action, a search active function if we can define a function from set to set B, which is A. 199 00:23:48,300 --> 00:23:53,100 In other words, every element of B gets hit by an arrow. 200 00:23:53,100 --> 00:23:59,460 Then we can say that the commonality of pay must be at least as great as the code Nancy at the OK. 201 00:23:59,460 --> 00:24:02,190 And that's that's normally enough for our purposes. 202 00:24:02,190 --> 00:24:09,540 We don't go to the trouble of trying to define objection a one to one correspondence that in many cases, 203 00:24:09,540 --> 00:24:15,780 would be a lot more complicated and unnecessarily so we'll see that quite shortly. 204 00:24:15,780 --> 00:24:27,040 Now, clearly, if you can define a subjection both ways, then on Hume's principle, the two commonalities should be the same. 205 00:24:27,040 --> 00:24:36,580 OK, now one very important special case, if a suggestion can be defined from the set of natural numbers to any set, 206 00:24:36,580 --> 00:24:41,620 then we say that that stuff is countable or innumerable, in other words. 207 00:24:41,620 --> 00:24:49,090 So we've got a function that goes from the natural numbers. Each natural number is mapped onto an element of this set. 208 00:24:49,090 --> 00:24:55,150 Every single element of that set is hit by at least one natural number, at least one of these arrows from a natural number. 209 00:24:55,150 --> 00:25:00,070 Right. So you can imagine in principle, 210 00:25:00,070 --> 00:25:09,760 writing down the elements of this set in order start according to the natural number which mapped onto them the first, the second or the 4.0. 211 00:25:09,760 --> 00:25:13,660 Now, some of those elements may occur multiple times in the list. 212 00:25:13,660 --> 00:25:18,130 That doesn't matter. We've said we're going to make do with a surge action. 213 00:25:18,130 --> 00:25:27,070 But every single element of that set should be there somewhere in the list if we have correctly defined as objective function. 214 00:25:27,070 --> 00:25:32,470 So we can enumerate the list in the sense of listed in principle because it's infinite. 215 00:25:32,470 --> 00:25:37,840 So we can't actually in practise, but in principle we can. OK. 216 00:25:37,840 --> 00:25:43,540 I've already thought about that. So one of the results that Cantor proved, rather surprisingly, 217 00:25:43,540 --> 00:25:49,390 is that the set of rational numbers and the set of algebraic numbers are both innumerable. 218 00:25:49,390 --> 00:26:03,850 So we're going to see how that works. OK, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as a fraction of integers expressed as a decimal. 219 00:26:03,850 --> 00:26:11,770 If you take a decimal number, a number is rational if and only if that decimal eventually recurs. 220 00:26:11,770 --> 00:26:17,200 So, for example, three point not not not not not not more recurring. 221 00:26:17,200 --> 00:26:28,660 That's the rational 7.5 no more recurring nought point six 666, etc. nought point three six seven three six seven three six seven. 222 00:26:28,660 --> 00:26:35,680 All of these are rational numbers. Now, it's actually pretty easy to show this. 223 00:26:35,680 --> 00:26:39,820 Take that last example nought point three six seven three six seven three six seven, 224 00:26:39,820 --> 00:26:46,510 etc. You can see that that is actually the sum of the geometric series. 225 00:26:46,510 --> 00:26:54,190 OK, you've got 367 over a thousand. That's that Mate Plus three, six seven over a million. 226 00:26:54,190 --> 00:27:00,370 That's that plus three six seven over a billion, which is that the and so on. 227 00:27:00,370 --> 00:27:09,550 So you've got a series in which each each item in the series is 1000 less than the item before. 228 00:27:09,550 --> 00:27:20,470 And you can easily that some geometric geometric progression using this formula, the first element divided by one minus the common ratio. 229 00:27:20,470 --> 00:27:27,160 And that means that some of that will be 367 over 9-9-9. 230 00:27:27,160 --> 00:27:35,320 OK. So any recurring decimal basically is going to be a rational number. 231 00:27:35,320 --> 00:27:46,690 When we're talking about irrational numbers, we're talking about decimals that go on and on forever, but do not actually recur. 232 00:27:46,690 --> 00:28:01,660 OK, now you might then think that the number of rational numbers will be hugely greater than the number of integers taken at the set of integers. 233 00:28:01,660 --> 00:28:05,800 Let's just talk about positive integers for the moment. 234 00:28:05,800 --> 00:28:13,120 One two three four five six seven And so between one and two, there are zillions of rational numbers, right? 235 00:28:13,120 --> 00:28:18,610 One followed by any proper fraction you get a mention is going to be a rational number. 236 00:28:18,610 --> 00:28:24,760 You know, one and seven twelfths or whatever is going to be a rational when you've got all these huge number of rational 237 00:28:24,760 --> 00:28:29,530 numbers between one and two and then you've got the same number between two and three and three and four. 238 00:28:29,530 --> 00:28:39,700 How can it be as Cantor claims that the set of rational numbers, all rational numbers has no more elements than the set of integers? 239 00:28:39,700 --> 00:28:40,720 Well, 240 00:28:40,720 --> 00:28:55,180 let's apply whose principle and very famous argument we set out all the rational numbers in an infinite array of clearly infinite in both directions. 241 00:28:55,180 --> 00:29:01,960 OK. So you can see that the first row has a denominator of one. 242 00:29:01,960 --> 00:29:10,150 The second row has a denominator of two. Third row has to nominate the three, and so the numerator is are in the column. 243 00:29:10,150 --> 00:29:14,080 So the first column has a numerator of one. 244 00:29:14,080 --> 00:29:18,250 The second column has a numerator to the third column as a new range of three. 245 00:29:18,250 --> 00:29:29,410 And so every fraction of positive integers is going to occur somewhere in that array. 246 00:29:29,410 --> 00:29:38,260 Agreed. And moreover, whatever fraction you care to name, it's actually pretty easy to say where in that array it look. 247 00:29:38,260 --> 00:29:49,780 So there's no mystery here. OK, now what we do, we put these fractions in a sequence starting from here. 248 00:29:49,780 --> 00:29:57,160 Then that one, then that one in that one, then that one in that one following the red line. 249 00:29:57,160 --> 00:30:09,520 And you can see that if we carry on in that pattern sooner or later, every single fraction in that array will be taken. 250 00:30:09,520 --> 00:30:20,320 Agree. So in and again, it's not that difficult actually to work out a formula which will tell you at what point in the sequence it will arise. 251 00:30:20,320 --> 00:30:28,720 So we've defined a suggestion, a suggestion from the natural numbers to the fractions. 252 00:30:28,720 --> 00:30:31,690 I've not spelt it out, but it's implicit here. 253 00:30:31,690 --> 00:30:40,180 You can see f of one is one over one effort to two over one after three is one half so that the F function is 254 00:30:40,180 --> 00:30:51,460 simply taking any natural number and mapping it to whichever fraction occurs at that point along the the red line. 255 00:30:51,460 --> 00:30:56,500 So it turns out you can put all the rational numbers in a list. 256 00:30:56,500 --> 00:31:06,220 An infinite list, of course, but that means there are no more natural numbers, so no more rational numbers than there are natural numbers you can pet. 257 00:31:06,220 --> 00:31:12,540 You can define this objection, so we list all of the fractions. 258 00:31:12,540 --> 00:31:18,490 And that's the start of it. Our suggestion maps one to the first of these two to the second three to the third. 259 00:31:18,490 --> 00:31:28,570 As we've seen. A curious fact about this is that every single fraction in that list occurs not just once, but an infinity of times. 260 00:31:28,570 --> 00:31:37,690 I mean, consider the fraction one over three. That's the same as two over six three overnight for over 12. 261 00:31:37,690 --> 00:31:45,700 So you've got this amazing result that that a list in which every single possible fraction 262 00:31:45,700 --> 00:31:54,400 occurs an infinity of times still contains no more elements than the number of natural numbers. 263 00:31:54,400 --> 00:31:58,990 You might be wondering what happens with negatives? Well, if you want to include negative fractions, you just alternate. 264 00:31:58,990 --> 00:32:06,410 Okay? It just means the list will be spaced out twice as much. 265 00:32:06,410 --> 00:32:14,450 OK, so a natural thought at this point would be, well, maybe it's not so surprising. 266 00:32:14,450 --> 00:32:21,320 OK. I mean, infinity is infinity. You've got an infinite number of natural numbers, an infinite number of rational numbers. 267 00:32:21,320 --> 00:32:26,160 Why should it be a surprise that these come out to be the same? 268 00:32:26,160 --> 00:32:37,830 Well, to see the impact of countless result, we need to look at irrational numbers, and I'm just going to introduce the most famous of these, 269 00:32:37,830 --> 00:32:46,260 perhaps it's a beautiful proof, I think really quite elegant, and I think it dates back to Euclid. 270 00:32:46,260 --> 00:32:52,710 Square two cannot be expressed as a fraction of integers. The square root of two is not a rational number. 271 00:32:52,710 --> 00:33:03,300 Amazingly, it's very easy to prove. Suppose that the square root of two is equal to m over n where N and N integers with no common factors. 272 00:33:03,300 --> 00:33:08,820 Now, do you agree? But if f if Root two can be written as a fraction of integers, 273 00:33:08,820 --> 00:33:15,690 then it is possible to write it as a fraction of integers in which the numerator and the denominator have no common factors, right? 274 00:33:15,690 --> 00:33:24,540 You just cancel them. OK. Square both sides of this and you get two equals n squared over in square. 275 00:33:24,540 --> 00:33:28,620 Multiply both sides by n squared. You get to square and then square. 276 00:33:28,620 --> 00:33:34,440 So it follows that and square. There's an even number. Yeah. 277 00:33:34,440 --> 00:33:44,350 Now, if the square is even the square root must be even two because any old number has an odd square. 278 00:33:44,350 --> 00:33:49,920 If you take an old number, we're talking about integers here, say to K +1 and you square it, 279 00:33:49,920 --> 00:33:54,090 you get for K squared plus Fourcade plus one, which is creating an odd number. 280 00:33:54,090 --> 00:33:59,430 So if you've got an even square, you must have an even number that's being squared. 281 00:33:59,430 --> 00:34:10,320 So it follows that n we had n squared is even now we know that Emmys even but his name is even n can be written as two K for some K integer. 282 00:34:10,320 --> 00:34:17,580 And that means that m squared is four k squared and we know that m squared is to n squared. 283 00:34:17,580 --> 00:34:25,560 It follows then that n squared is going to be even as well, from which it follows by the previous reasoning. 284 00:34:25,560 --> 00:34:31,170 The end is even so, we end up with the conclusion Emmys even and then is even which is a contradiction 285 00:34:31,170 --> 00:34:35,500 because we started with the assumption that men have no factor in common. 286 00:34:35,500 --> 00:34:38,160 Turns out they have to have two income. 287 00:34:38,160 --> 00:34:51,420 So if we start with the assumption that the square root of two can be written as a fraction of integers, we end up contradicting that assumption. 288 00:34:51,420 --> 00:34:56,120 Therefore, Root two is not a rational number. 289 00:34:56,120 --> 00:35:11,030 OK, so that shows that the fractions of integers do not exhaust all the numbers, there are numbers like root to which cannot be written in that form. 290 00:35:11,030 --> 00:35:14,780 But the square root of two is at least an algebraic number. 291 00:35:14,780 --> 00:35:23,720 The square root of two is a number that can be written as a solution of an equation in one variable with integer coefficients. 292 00:35:23,720 --> 00:35:30,290 Right. So x squared equals to the solution. 293 00:35:30,290 --> 00:35:34,430 Root two is called an algebraic number. 294 00:35:34,430 --> 00:35:41,630 It's not rational, but it's algebraic. An irrational number is straightforwardly algebraic and over. 295 00:35:41,630 --> 00:35:49,310 B is the solution of the equation. B X equals a any square root or n through to the rational number is algebraic. 296 00:35:49,310 --> 00:35:59,330 As we've seen in the case of square root of two. So we've been forced to acknowledge that there are numbers beyond rational numbers. 297 00:35:59,330 --> 00:36:03,290 Not every number can be written as a fraction of integers. 298 00:36:03,290 --> 00:36:13,230 OK, let's accept then, that there are these other numbers which are solutions two equations with integer coefficients. 299 00:36:13,230 --> 00:36:16,940 And will that suffice? Well, maybe it will. 300 00:36:16,940 --> 00:36:26,960 Maybe it won't. We'll come to that shortly. But let's show for good measure that the algebraic numbers are innumerable numeral. 301 00:36:26,960 --> 00:36:38,270 So just like the rational numbers, we can actually put all the algebraic numbers, which include the rational numbers into a list to prove this. 302 00:36:38,270 --> 00:36:44,810 Let's suppose we got an algebraic equation. Here's a general form of an algebraic equation. 303 00:36:44,810 --> 00:36:49,350 And what are we going to do? Is define the rank of the equation as this. 304 00:36:49,350 --> 00:36:57,410 OK, now don't worry about this. All right, just just take this as a useful way of listing all these equations. 305 00:36:57,410 --> 00:37:04,820 So what we want is a number which indicates, as it were, how big the numbers are in this equation. 306 00:37:04,820 --> 00:37:13,790 So what we're doing, we taking them the constant turn and taking it to absolute value so we don't care whether it's positive or negative. 307 00:37:13,790 --> 00:37:20,930 The positive value of the coefficient of X, the positive value of the coefficient of X squared, etc., etc., 308 00:37:20,930 --> 00:37:31,720 etc. We're adding the absolute value of all the coefficients together and then adding to that the highest degree of X. 309 00:37:31,720 --> 00:37:40,250 OK. That gives us a number. It's clearly going to be a positive number. 310 00:37:40,250 --> 00:37:49,780 Yeah. Very sensible equation can't be negative because we're taking absolute advantage of time. 311 00:37:49,780 --> 00:37:57,620 Now here's the crucial thing. Suppose you take all the equations that have rank three. 312 00:37:57,620 --> 00:38:02,930 Say there will be a finite number of those and you can list what they are. 313 00:38:02,930 --> 00:38:08,350 So and we can order them first by end, then by the various coefficient. 314 00:38:08,350 --> 00:38:22,040 So this is easiest understood if we take examples. So these equations have rank two because this has coefficients minus one and zero. 315 00:38:22,040 --> 00:38:26,120 So the absolute value of minus one is one at zero. 316 00:38:26,120 --> 00:38:31,820 We get one and the highest degree of X is one, so we get one plus one to rank two. 317 00:38:31,820 --> 00:38:36,980 This has rank two as well. Those are the only two equations of rank two, right? 318 00:38:36,980 --> 00:38:42,050 One of them has a coefficient of minus one before x one has a coefficient of one. 319 00:38:42,050 --> 00:38:51,350 For equations of rank three, there are more of those, including a couple of quadratic. 320 00:38:51,350 --> 00:39:01,670 In order to get rank three here, since the highest degree of X is two, we're only allowed one as the coefficient, so it better be minus one or one. 321 00:39:01,670 --> 00:39:05,660 So those are the only two quadratic that get rank three. 322 00:39:05,660 --> 00:39:10,730 But you can see we're getting more of the linear equations. 323 00:39:10,730 --> 00:39:22,230 You get the idea. So, so the rank simply measures as it were the size of the coefficients of the equation linked with the degree of the equation. 324 00:39:22,230 --> 00:39:28,040 And I haven't. I've just started off with rank four. OK. 325 00:39:28,040 --> 00:39:35,360 So we've got a way of listing all the algebraic equations. 326 00:39:35,360 --> 00:39:43,880 First of all, we list those with rank two, then those with rank three, then those with rank four, then between five and within each group. 327 00:39:43,880 --> 00:39:55,160 We list them in the order just specified, awarded first by and then by and then by eight minus one and so on, and finally by a zero. 328 00:39:55,160 --> 00:40:03,500 OK, so imagine we've got this infinite list of all the all the possible algebraic equations. 329 00:40:03,500 --> 00:40:08,780 Now, every algebraic equation has it most in solutions. 330 00:40:08,780 --> 00:40:16,580 So if any is the highest power of X in the equation, you know, quadratic equation can have at most two solutions. 331 00:40:16,580 --> 00:40:27,500 Imagine solving all these equations, those that are solvable at any rate and listing the roots of the equation in numerical order. 332 00:40:27,500 --> 00:40:33,860 I've mentioned here you could put complex numbers into this if you want, but we're not thinking about complex numbers here. 333 00:40:33,860 --> 00:40:42,770 So now we can make a list that will include all the algebraic numbers because we've got this list of all the algebraic equations. 334 00:40:42,770 --> 00:40:52,730 And then for each of those equations, in order, we list all of the roots of that equation again in numerical order and every single algebra number, 335 00:40:52,730 --> 00:41:01,220 every number, which is a root as of any one of those equations will appear somewhere in that infinite list. 336 00:41:01,220 --> 00:41:09,650 So as before, we can define a suggestion and QED quod erat demonstrated to me proves what we set out to prove. 337 00:41:09,650 --> 00:41:18,950 You can actually produce an infinite list of algebraic numbers, which contains every single algebraic number. 338 00:41:18,950 --> 00:41:25,070 So there are no more algebraic numbers than there are integers. 339 00:41:25,070 --> 00:41:31,280 OK, so again, you might think maybe this isn't a surprise. 340 00:41:31,280 --> 00:41:33,230 Infinity is infinity. 341 00:41:33,230 --> 00:41:44,120 Maybe all infinite sets are of the same size, but now we come to transcendental numbers, and these are irrational numbers that are not algebraic. 342 00:41:44,120 --> 00:41:53,360 Okay, piety of the most famous examples. But if trigonometric functions often yield them as well. 343 00:41:53,360 --> 00:41:56,450 Notice, by the way, that when we're dealing with trigonometric functions, 344 00:41:56,450 --> 00:42:07,220 we standardly think of the angle in radians, not in degrees, so that that fundamentally changes things. 345 00:42:07,220 --> 00:42:11,630 OK. So there are transcendental numbers. 346 00:42:11,630 --> 00:42:20,480 There are numbers that are not roots of a algebraic equations. 347 00:42:20,480 --> 00:42:27,560 Surprisingly, although Pi and E may be the only familiar ones or the most familiar ones. 348 00:42:27,560 --> 00:42:33,940 It turns out that to a rough approximation, all numbers are transcendental. 349 00:42:33,940 --> 00:42:44,020 So this is due to a proof by Cantor, which we now going to see famous dive in the truth. 350 00:42:44,020 --> 00:42:51,460 So Cantor showed that real numbers in general cannot be put into an infinite list. 351 00:42:51,460 --> 00:42:57,550 Rational numbers can, algebraic numbers can, real numbers can't. 352 00:42:57,550 --> 00:43:00,700 And again, we've got a proof by reductio out absurdum. 353 00:43:00,700 --> 00:43:07,810 We start with the assumption that they can be put into a list and then we show that that's impossible. 354 00:43:07,810 --> 00:43:14,860 So let's suppose that the set of real numbers were in fact innumerable could be put into an infinite list. 355 00:43:14,860 --> 00:43:22,270 In that case, it would A44 why it would be true that all the real numbers between zero and one could be put into an infinite list. 356 00:43:22,270 --> 00:43:28,810 Yes. Let's just restrict our attention to that small subset of the real numbers between zero and one. 357 00:43:28,810 --> 00:43:36,730 Ignore all the infinite others. Imagine that they have been put into an infinite list. 358 00:43:36,730 --> 00:43:40,120 So here's the list. That's the first of them. 359 00:43:40,120 --> 00:43:49,630 Second, third, fourth, fifth and so on. And one is the first digit after the decimal point of the first number in the list. 360 00:43:49,630 --> 00:43:54,700 8.4 is the fourth digit off the decimal point of the second number in the list. 361 00:43:54,700 --> 00:44:02,320 And so everyone happy with that. So now look down the long diagonal there. 362 00:44:02,320 --> 00:44:06,400 What I've done, I've chosen the first digit of the first number in the list. 363 00:44:06,400 --> 00:44:11,860 The second digit of the second number of the list. The third digit at the third number in the list and so on. 364 00:44:11,860 --> 00:44:22,090 What we're now going to do is construct a number, a decimal number, which differs from each of those. 365 00:44:22,090 --> 00:44:31,030 So in the fourth place, we're going to choose a digit, which is different from eight four four in the fifth place. 366 00:44:31,030 --> 00:44:36,370 We're going to choose a digit different from a five, five and so on. 367 00:44:36,370 --> 00:44:43,780 Do you agree that if we do that, we will end up with a number which differs from every single number in the list 368 00:44:43,780 --> 00:44:51,820 because it will differ from the number in the eighth place after the decimal point? 369 00:44:51,820 --> 00:44:57,790 OK, so we can define this number, we can call it number C in honour of Cantor. 370 00:44:57,790 --> 00:45:06,670 Let's just say that if the end digit of the ninth number in that list is five, 371 00:45:06,670 --> 00:45:12,030 then the digit of our specially defined number is going to be made zero. 372 00:45:12,030 --> 00:45:19,060 But otherwise, we're going to make it five. So we're going to we're defining a number here. 373 00:45:19,060 --> 00:45:22,840 Every single digit is either going to be zero or five. 374 00:45:22,840 --> 00:45:32,860 But we fixed it so that if the f number in the list happens to have a five at the crucial point, we have a zero. 375 00:45:32,860 --> 00:45:39,360 And if that number has a zero, we have a five. In fact, if it has anything else, we have a thought. 376 00:45:39,360 --> 00:45:46,170 So the number that we defined is going to differ from the entry number in the list at the ninth decimal point. 377 00:45:46,170 --> 00:45:54,000 So effectively what we're doing, we're writing out a number where if you go to say the fourth digit of that number, 378 00:45:54,000 --> 00:46:00,450 you can be quite sure that it will be different from the fourth digit of the fourth number on the list. 379 00:46:00,450 --> 00:46:07,560 It will therefore in the same way it will differ at some point from every single number in that list. 380 00:46:07,560 --> 00:46:12,930 But we started off with the assumption that every single real number is in that list. 381 00:46:12,930 --> 00:46:18,930 We've just defined a number which a real number, which is not in that list. 382 00:46:18,930 --> 00:46:28,220 So we've got a contradiction. This is a for obvious reasons, called a diagonal argument. 383 00:46:28,220 --> 00:46:35,480 It's an argument that works by taking two dimensions of variation and providing some construction that runs down the diagonal. 384 00:46:35,480 --> 00:46:42,080 We're going to be looking at some other diagonal arguments. A very famous one is the proof of cantors theorem. 385 00:46:42,080 --> 00:46:51,750 For any set, the powerset of a that is the set of subsets of a always has a greater carnality than a itself. 386 00:46:51,750 --> 00:47:03,750 So suppose, for example, you've got three people, how many different sets of those three people can you make? 387 00:47:03,750 --> 00:47:09,930 Well, the first person can either be in or out of the set. 388 00:47:09,930 --> 00:47:14,760 Yeah. So that's two possibilities for each of those possibilities. 389 00:47:14,760 --> 00:47:20,070 The second person can be in or out of the set. So that gives you two times two. 390 00:47:20,070 --> 00:47:25,380 And for each one of those possibilities, the third person can either be in or out of the set, which gives you eight. 391 00:47:25,380 --> 00:47:31,500 Yeah. So you get eight subsets. So in general, with a finite set, if you've got an elements, 392 00:47:31,500 --> 00:47:39,630 the number of subsets is two to the end because basically every new element doubles up the possible subsets that you can have. 393 00:47:39,630 --> 00:47:45,590 Bear in mind, the null set is a subset of the set itself is a subset. OK. 394 00:47:45,590 --> 00:47:55,790 So with finite sets, it's very obvious that the set of subsets in this case, the set of those eight subsets has more elements than the initial set. 395 00:47:55,790 --> 00:47:59,660 The set of three is that true for infinite sets? 396 00:47:59,660 --> 00:48:09,770 Will Cantor showed that it was the very nice proof, so let's suppose, first of all, as in innumerable sets. 397 00:48:09,770 --> 00:48:17,420 In other words, it's a set where we can list all the elements of the set in a list, an infinite list fine. 398 00:48:17,420 --> 00:48:22,880 But those are the elements of the set nested along the top. 399 00:48:22,880 --> 00:48:36,500 And let's suppose that we can define a subjective function from each element of that list, 400 00:48:36,500 --> 00:48:43,640 which which hits as it were every single subset of that set. 401 00:48:43,640 --> 00:48:55,760 So if a value one will be some subset of that set and it will be the one to which A1 is mapped by the suggestion. 402 00:48:55,760 --> 00:49:04,790 So we've got a subjective function. It maps each element of the set onto some subset of the set, and it's a subjective function, 403 00:49:04,790 --> 00:49:10,100 which means that every single subset gets hit at least once. 404 00:49:10,100 --> 00:49:22,760 Is that OK? Now imagine then that we set up a table like this where here we've got the subset that to which A1 matches. 405 00:49:22,760 --> 00:49:27,080 Here's the subset to which a two maps. Here's the subset to which a three maps. 406 00:49:27,080 --> 00:49:35,750 And so and we've put a tick or a cross to indicate which elements of the set are actually in that subset. 407 00:49:35,750 --> 00:49:40,970 OK. Don't imagine there's any authority in the ticks and crosses I've put here. 408 00:49:40,970 --> 00:49:48,500 It's entirely arbitrary. OK? I've just said, let's suppose that the first four to have this pattern, they might have a completely different pattern. 409 00:49:48,500 --> 00:49:53,420 It doesn't matter what we're we going to do is go down the diagonal, 410 00:49:53,420 --> 00:50:02,180 look at that diagonal and suppose we consider the set of elements that have crosses down the long diagonal. 411 00:50:02,180 --> 00:50:07,190 OK, that's in this case. That's an A3 and A4. 412 00:50:07,190 --> 00:50:09,380 They're the ones that have crosses down the long diagonal. 413 00:50:09,380 --> 00:50:19,600 In other words, those are the ones that do not belong to the set to which they are mapped by our surge action. 414 00:50:19,600 --> 00:50:29,200 Imagine that we take all of those elements which have a cross in the long diagonal of the former subset of them, 415 00:50:29,200 --> 00:50:39,880 so we form the set of all the elements which are not contained in the subset to which they are mapped. 416 00:50:39,880 --> 00:50:46,570 By similar reasoning to cantors, diagonal of the the diagonal arguments about real numbers, 417 00:50:46,570 --> 00:50:52,270 and we have thus constructed a subset which is not present in the list. 418 00:50:52,270 --> 00:51:03,820 So again, we get a contradiction. It is not possible to have a subjective function from an infinite set when the any set of innumerable, 419 00:51:03,820 --> 00:51:10,660 any innumerable set of objects onto the subsets of that set. 420 00:51:10,660 --> 00:51:16,480 That's quite tricky. This is something that to it's worth thinking about. 421 00:51:16,480 --> 00:51:20,500 You know, the the text of the slides actually explains it. 422 00:51:20,500 --> 00:51:33,580 If you find it difficult as some eyes suggest you do, which isn't surprising to try with some examples with small sets, see how they work out. 423 00:51:33,580 --> 00:51:40,850 See how you fill in the grid. And that will probably help. 424 00:51:40,850 --> 00:51:45,020 Now, in fact, the proof of counsel's theorem doesn't rely on innumerable. 425 00:51:45,020 --> 00:51:45,740 Here we did. 426 00:51:45,740 --> 00:51:58,760 I mean, the only I was only able to set up this grid on the assumption that our objects here, the set of a was innumerable, but quite generally, 427 00:51:58,760 --> 00:52:03,440 where a is any set at all innumerable or not, 428 00:52:03,440 --> 00:52:17,810 we can think of the set of elements of a which are not elements of the subset to which they have been mapped. 429 00:52:17,810 --> 00:52:23,320 And in fact, we get exactly the same kind of contradiction. 430 00:52:23,320 --> 00:52:33,170 It's this this subset, the set of elements which do not belong to the subset to which their map cannot be in the range of function f, 431 00:52:33,170 --> 00:52:41,210 because if X is fixed for any X, then if X is it a subset is an element of X. 432 00:52:41,210 --> 00:52:48,440 It turns out that X also cannot be a sub in an element to this. 433 00:52:48,440 --> 00:52:57,920 So this implies that the power sets of an infinite set must have a card analogy strictly greater than that set. 434 00:52:57,920 --> 00:53:07,820 And I'm going to refer you here to Petzold, who draws some lessons from this about the commonality of the continuum and other infinite numbers. 435 00:53:07,820 --> 00:53:16,430 I mean, effectively, this means that if you start with some set and then you take the set of subsets, 436 00:53:16,430 --> 00:53:22,070 you have to move to a larger number, whether that set was finite or infinite. 437 00:53:22,070 --> 00:53:31,430 So if you start with a set of natural numbers and then you take the set of some subsets of natural numbers, you must get to a greater infinity. 438 00:53:31,430 --> 00:53:38,510 And if you then take the set of subsets of that set, you must get to a greater infinity again and so on and so on and so on. 439 00:53:38,510 --> 00:53:45,800 So not only do we have at least two infinities, namely the number of natural numbers and the number of rational numbers. 440 00:53:45,800 --> 00:53:50,180 Actually, there's an infinite number of infinity. 441 00:53:50,180 --> 00:53:57,000 You can see why some people were rather dubious about cantors theory, but turns out to be to all make sense. 442 00:53:57,000 --> 00:54:04,570 You know, you can't generate contradictions from it. So it's very widely accepted. 443 00:54:04,570 --> 00:54:11,140 Finally, I'm going to end with an important consequences consequence of this for philosophy of logic and mathematics. 444 00:54:11,140 --> 00:54:20,050 Really, very, very important indeed. Bertrand Russell contemplated cantors arguments and you can see how close cantors argument gets to this, 445 00:54:20,050 --> 00:54:26,800 and hence Russell thought about the set of all sets that are not members of themselves. 446 00:54:26,800 --> 00:54:35,170 So, for example, take the set of cats. The set of cats is not itself a cat, so it's not a member of itself. 447 00:54:35,170 --> 00:54:44,830 Great. Whereas the set of all sets is itself a set and is therefore an element of itself. 448 00:54:44,830 --> 00:54:47,080 Take all the sets that are like the set of cats, 449 00:54:47,080 --> 00:54:55,690 all the sets that are not members of themselves think the set of everything that is not an element of itself doesn't mean it can't be a set. 450 00:54:55,690 --> 00:55:01,090 But if it is a set, it's not an element of itself, is it? 451 00:55:01,090 --> 00:55:08,360 Or is it not an element of itself? Well, if it is an element of itself, then it's not an element of itself. 452 00:55:08,360 --> 00:55:12,370 If it's not an element of itself, then it is an element of it. So you get a contradiction. 453 00:55:12,370 --> 00:55:18,370 It's rather similar to the paradox of the village barber who shapes all and only those men who do not shave themselves. 454 00:55:18,370 --> 00:55:25,720 Does he shave himself? OK, well, you can get round that one because you can say either there just is no such barber. 455 00:55:25,720 --> 00:55:32,710 It's an impossibility. Or you can more coming in to say, Well, maybe the barber was a woman. 456 00:55:32,710 --> 00:55:42,520 But the problem with the set of all sets that are not members of themselves is that it seems to be defined in such a straightforward way that to say, 457 00:55:42,520 --> 00:55:49,570 Oh, there's no such thing makes us wonder, Well, why not? 458 00:55:49,570 --> 00:55:53,020 We know what it is for a set to be a member of itself. 459 00:55:53,020 --> 00:55:57,790 Why can't we simply take all the assets that are not members themselves and put them in a big set? 460 00:55:57,790 --> 00:56:02,650 What stops us doing that? Well, it leads to a contradiction. Yeah, OK. 461 00:56:02,650 --> 00:56:10,930 It leads to a contradiction. But if that leads to a contradiction based on such straightforward ideas, where else might there be contradictions? 462 00:56:10,930 --> 00:56:17,440 And you can see the effect that this had on Friday, Russell wrote to Fraser in 1982. 463 00:56:17,440 --> 00:56:24,940 Explaining the paradox, Schrager wrote back to Russell six days later. 464 00:56:24,940 --> 00:56:34,630 So he probably only just received it. Your discovery of the contradiction has surprised me beyond words, and I should almost like to say, 465 00:56:34,630 --> 00:56:43,390 let me thunderstruck because it is rocked the ground on which I'm meant to build arithmetic. 466 00:56:43,390 --> 00:56:54,340 So there we're going to end today. Next lecture, we will see another phenomenal rocking of the ground in the form of girdles theorem. 467 00:56:54,340 --> 00:56:56,560 See you then. Thank you.