1 00:00:10,530 --> 00:00:17,820 So this week's topic is mainly knowledge, with a little bit more to say to round scepticism. 2 00:00:17,820 --> 00:00:26,900 Our four luminaries there. We've got Freddie Air, AJ Air, who was professor at New College when I was an undergraduate, 3 00:00:26,900 --> 00:00:34,920 edman getting a famous for writing a three page paper in the Journal analysis in 1963. 4 00:00:34,920 --> 00:00:41,370 I'm not sure whether he's published anything since, but it suffice to make him very famous. 5 00:00:41,370 --> 00:00:45,930 Then we've got Hillary Putnam, who will come to the very end. 6 00:00:45,930 --> 00:00:49,590 And Tim Williamson on the right, who is professor here. 7 00:00:49,590 --> 00:00:58,170 A successor to AJ. Tim's work isn't actually going to feature in this lecture or indeed in the readings you have. 8 00:00:58,170 --> 00:01:04,470 But he's one of the most prominent epistemology states in the world. So it's as well to know that he's around. 9 00:01:04,470 --> 00:01:09,240 If you find yourself giving a paper and you see him in the audience, beware. 10 00:01:09,240 --> 00:01:17,700 He's universally feared for the sharpness and precision of his questions. 11 00:01:17,700 --> 00:01:21,150 OK, so we've seen some sceptical arguments. 12 00:01:21,150 --> 00:01:30,780 Most famously, those of Descartes and those sorts of arguments, rather suggest that if we put a threshold for knowledge very high, 13 00:01:30,780 --> 00:01:36,210 then we're quite likely to be driven to the conclusion that we do not know anything at all. 14 00:01:36,210 --> 00:01:43,650 Descartes own answers don't seem to work very well. Other answers are all very controversial. 15 00:01:43,650 --> 00:01:49,260 It's rather tempting to try to get round this problem by redefining the notion 16 00:01:49,260 --> 00:01:55,160 of knowledge to provide a useful distinction amongst the beliefs we have. 17 00:01:55,160 --> 00:02:03,750 Maybe none of them, or only very, very few like I exist, will actually reach the highest threshold. 18 00:02:03,750 --> 00:02:09,360 But surely it makes sense to try to define a more moderate, more reasonable threshold, 19 00:02:09,360 --> 00:02:16,640 because we do want to distinguish between things that we know in a perfectly ordinary sense and things that we do not know. 20 00:02:16,640 --> 00:02:26,480 So we naturally get the question, what is knowledge? How should we understand the notion of knowledge? 21 00:02:26,480 --> 00:02:32,750 Now, questions of the form. What is X feature quite prominently in philosophy. 22 00:02:32,750 --> 00:02:39,470 If you go back to Plato and look in his dialogues, you'll see that Socrates is always asking this sort of question. 23 00:02:39,470 --> 00:02:47,150 In fact, it used to be the case. I think that people thought of this sort of thing as absolutely paradigmatic of what philosophers do. 24 00:02:47,150 --> 00:02:52,130 Philosophers search for essences by trying to define things. 25 00:02:52,130 --> 00:02:55,940 I don't think you'll find it's nearly as prominent these days, 26 00:02:55,940 --> 00:03:03,500 but such questions still come up quite a lot in topics like personal identity or freedom. 27 00:03:03,500 --> 00:03:12,790 What do we mean by freedom? What is freedom? No such questions, if you think about it's a rather puzzling. 28 00:03:12,790 --> 00:03:21,160 Because they could just be asking, when do we apply the word X, where X is freedom, knowledge or whatever? 29 00:03:21,160 --> 00:03:32,290 But that sort of question seems to be just about our use of language that we want to go deeper than that to ask what is a genuine case of X? 30 00:03:32,290 --> 00:03:38,110 If that question isn't just about our use of language, then what is it? 31 00:03:38,110 --> 00:03:47,860 It seems rather peculiar. What could knowledge be other than what we refer to using the word knowledge? 32 00:03:47,860 --> 00:03:51,790 So let me give you an example. Take the discipline of geography. 33 00:03:51,790 --> 00:03:58,870 Suppose that the study of geography started out as the study of places in terms of their location, 34 00:03:58,870 --> 00:04:04,420 physical characteristics, mineral, mineral resources, the natural environment, that sort of thing. 35 00:04:04,420 --> 00:04:09,760 I'm not sure whether that was true, but let's suppose that it was then over time, 36 00:04:09,760 --> 00:04:16,810 people became interested in things like land use, economic considerations, maybe even culture. 37 00:04:16,810 --> 00:04:22,840 And if you study geography now, you will find that culture is one of the things that gets studied. 38 00:04:22,840 --> 00:04:32,290 Now, you can imagine someone saying, that's all very well. You now study culture as part of geography, but his culture really part of geography. 39 00:04:32,290 --> 00:04:36,640 Does geography really include cultural things? 40 00:04:36,640 --> 00:04:47,530 Well, if the word geography is now used to cover cultural matters, amongst others, then sure, the discipline of geography includes culture. 41 00:04:47,530 --> 00:04:50,430 How could it not? 42 00:04:50,430 --> 00:04:59,680 So it might well look as though the kinds of questions we're asking when we ask what is X, what is knowledge, just come down to language. 43 00:04:59,680 --> 00:05:07,110 And in the 1950s and 60s, Oxford philosophy was famously identified with ordinary language philosophy as though 44 00:05:07,110 --> 00:05:14,370 the purpose of philosophy was just getting clear about how we use ordinary language. 45 00:05:14,370 --> 00:05:20,600 If that were all there is to it, then it would be rather an uninteresting kind of question. 46 00:05:20,600 --> 00:05:26,000 But with most of the concepts that interest philosophers, there is something deeper at stake. 47 00:05:26,000 --> 00:05:34,310 Take the case of freedom, which we'll be looking at in a week or two, that we're not just interested in how we use the word freedom. 48 00:05:34,310 --> 00:05:43,160 We want to know what kinds of acts we should describe as free because the notion of freedom is tied to moral responsibility. 49 00:05:43,160 --> 00:05:53,020 We think it matters whether somebody is free. It could turn out that we describe actions as free when really from a God's eye point of view, 50 00:05:53,020 --> 00:05:59,620 then not maybe we described people as free in certain circumstances in ordinary life. 51 00:05:59,620 --> 00:06:05,950 But actually, if we knew about it, there's no moral responsibility there, no genuine freedom. 52 00:06:05,950 --> 00:06:13,500 So there is a deeper metaphysical question underlying the linguistic question. 53 00:06:13,500 --> 00:06:20,100 Now, likewise, in the case of knowledge, the concept of knowledge has a normative aspect when we say is knowledge. 54 00:06:20,100 --> 00:06:24,920 We're not just categorising it as something that is called knowledge. 55 00:06:24,920 --> 00:06:31,970 We're saying that it's reliable, that it has a certain authority. So it is possible to ask of a particular belief. 56 00:06:31,970 --> 00:06:36,890 Well, everyone says they know this. But is it really knowledge? 57 00:06:36,890 --> 00:06:46,320 Do they really know it? Again, a similar issue arises with Strauss' response to the problem of a problem of induction. 58 00:06:46,320 --> 00:06:54,240 On your induction reading list. He famously says that inductive methods just are what we mean by reasonable. 59 00:06:54,240 --> 00:07:02,050 When we describe an inference about the world is reasonable, that just means it meets inductive standards. 60 00:07:02,050 --> 00:07:05,550 But a very well-known answer to Straughan is to say, hang on a minute. 61 00:07:05,550 --> 00:07:14,700 No. When we say that a method of inference is reasonable, we're not just saying that this is the kind of inference that everybody calls reasonable. 62 00:07:14,700 --> 00:07:25,840 We actually mean that it is reasonable that it has normative force, that this kind of inference really does convey assurance to the conclusion. 63 00:07:25,840 --> 00:07:31,600 The kind of conceptual analysis that we're doing on the concept of knowledge provides a nice example of this, 64 00:07:31,600 --> 00:07:34,720 and that's a good reason for having it in this general philosophy. 65 00:07:34,720 --> 00:07:46,470 Course, from this example, you can get an idea of the kinds of things that typically pop up in these sorts of discussions. 66 00:07:46,470 --> 00:07:53,060 So one of the things that often comes up is appealed to linguistic intuitions. 67 00:07:53,060 --> 00:08:01,460 Now, when people talk about intuition, it's sometimes a bit sloppy, as though they're saying, oh, well, this is just something, I think an intuition. 68 00:08:01,460 --> 00:08:10,120 You've got to accept it. But actually, linguistic intuitions have a particular authority, because if you're a native expert, 69 00:08:10,120 --> 00:08:16,020 speaker of your language, then certain things do just come naturally to you to say. 70 00:08:16,020 --> 00:08:20,840 And that does carry some authority that the standard use of language. 71 00:08:20,840 --> 00:08:30,380 Now, obviously, that doesn't necessarily tell you anything about philosophical truth, but it does keep you on the rails of using language correctly. 72 00:08:30,380 --> 00:08:37,890 Puzzle cases also feature a lot, as we'll see in this lecture. Some people call these intuition pumps. 73 00:08:37,890 --> 00:08:47,110 The idea of a puzzle case is that you sketch out some hypothetical scenario and then you ask, well, what would you say about that? 74 00:08:47,110 --> 00:08:53,230 And clearly, what you try to do is devise puzzle cases which steer your hearers intuitions 75 00:08:53,230 --> 00:08:58,000 in the way you want to take them so often you'll find in philosophical debate. 76 00:08:58,000 --> 00:09:03,590 Each side is producing puzzle cases to favour their own particular point of view. 77 00:09:03,590 --> 00:09:10,190 You'll find in personal identity, for example, puzzle cases feature quite highly. 78 00:09:10,190 --> 00:09:14,360 Then obviously we get argument and we get systematise Asian. 79 00:09:14,360 --> 00:09:23,410 We try to pull all these intuitions and thoughts together to make sense of them altogether. 80 00:09:23,410 --> 00:09:28,570 So let us now embark on a discussion of knowledge and its variants, 81 00:09:28,570 --> 00:09:33,700 trying to employ some of these methods to straighten out what we want to say about it. 82 00:09:33,700 --> 00:09:39,760 So, first of all, let's distinguish between three different kinds of knowledge, acquaintance. 83 00:09:39,760 --> 00:09:47,260 Knowing how and knowing that what we're interested in here is propositional knowledge, 84 00:09:47,260 --> 00:09:53,710 knowledge that p a strange phrase that you'll find philosophers use it quite a lot. 85 00:09:53,710 --> 00:09:57,880 So here's a proposition. Could be any old proposition. 86 00:09:57,880 --> 00:10:07,960 But notice, knowing that P is the case is quite different from having acquaintance with somebody or something or having practical knowledge. 87 00:10:07,960 --> 00:10:13,440 For example, I know how to ride a bike. I don't exactly know how I do it. 88 00:10:13,440 --> 00:10:19,220 I'm ignorant of all sorts of propositions that would explain how I managed to remain upright on a bike. 89 00:10:19,220 --> 00:10:31,658 But I have the practical knowledge that is I can actually do it.