1 00:00:10,540 --> 00:00:17,730 We've seen what Locke has to say about personal identity. 2 00:00:17,730 --> 00:00:25,620 Admittedly, only briefly, but you can see that he distinguishes between the identity of different things, 3 00:00:25,620 --> 00:00:32,610 in particular distinguishes between the identity of a physical organism and the person. 4 00:00:32,610 --> 00:00:43,370 He's got a clear motive for doing that because of the forensic importance of the notion of person, its relation to morality and desert and so forth. 5 00:00:43,370 --> 00:00:51,650 And he links personhood with consciousness. And therefore with memory. 6 00:00:51,650 --> 00:00:58,200 Now, Thomas Reed famously raised a problem case for Locke, which he put like this. 7 00:00:58,200 --> 00:01:03,150 Suppose you've got a young lieutenant in the Army. He can remember what he did as a child. 8 00:01:03,150 --> 00:01:11,170 Maybe, for example, he can remember stealing an apple. Maybe feels guilty about it. 9 00:01:11,170 --> 00:01:19,670 When he becomes a general. The general can remember what the lieutenant did, but he can't remember what the child did. 10 00:01:19,670 --> 00:01:24,370 He's completely forgotten about the Apple incident. 11 00:01:24,370 --> 00:01:32,620 Now, if memory constitutes personal identity, then it looks like the lieutenant is the same one, I'm the same person as the child. 12 00:01:32,620 --> 00:01:40,080 The general is one and the same person as the lieutenant. But the general is not the same person as the child. 13 00:01:40,080 --> 00:01:47,020 And that seems to be a contradiction because the notion of identity is supposed to be a transitive relation. 14 00:01:47,020 --> 00:01:51,820 That is, if X is identical with Y. And why is identical with Z? 15 00:01:51,820 --> 00:01:58,110 It follows that X is identical with Z. That seems to be a logical truth about the notion of identity. 16 00:01:58,110 --> 00:02:02,770 Indeed, it follows from Lightman's law. 17 00:02:02,770 --> 00:02:10,240 Well, there is a nice, elegant way of getting around this, so we introduce what's called the ancestral relation. 18 00:02:10,240 --> 00:02:18,580 You'll see. It's obvious why it's called the ancestral relation, because the classic example of this is the relation of being an ancestor. 19 00:02:18,580 --> 00:02:25,120 So look at this definition. X is an ancestor of Y if either. 20 00:02:25,120 --> 00:02:33,540 X is a parent of Y. Or X is a parent of an ancestor of Y. 21 00:02:33,540 --> 00:02:35,820 Now, when you first see that definition, you might think. 22 00:02:35,820 --> 00:02:43,230 Isn't that a bit odd because the word ancestor is not only appearing as the word to be defined. 23 00:02:43,230 --> 00:02:50,580 It's also appearing in the definition. Isn't that circular? Well, in a sense it is, but it's not viciously circular. 24 00:02:50,580 --> 00:02:59,150 And that's because we have the first clause as well. So suppose we want to identify who my ancestors are. 25 00:02:59,150 --> 00:03:05,350 Well, what this says is, first of all, my parents are ancestors. 26 00:03:05,350 --> 00:03:13,160 Okay, but then their parents and sisters, because they have parents of ancestors of mine. 27 00:03:13,160 --> 00:03:20,610 And then their parents or ancestors of mine. Because their parents of ancestors of mine and so on. 28 00:03:20,610 --> 00:03:27,300 So actually, it's very elegant, neat way of getting a recursive definition. 29 00:03:27,300 --> 00:03:31,140 The definition van sister appeals to the notion of ancestry itself. 30 00:03:31,140 --> 00:03:37,630 So it's recursive. But it's not viciously said. 31 00:03:37,630 --> 00:03:44,610 Now, consider that in the abstract, consider what we've done, we've taken the neat notion of parent, 32 00:03:44,610 --> 00:03:54,520 the relation of being a parent, and we have generated from that a more general relation that includes parenthood. 33 00:03:54,520 --> 00:04:03,570 But as it were, iterates it. So we call ancestor the ancestral relation of parent. 34 00:04:03,570 --> 00:04:09,020 Now, suppose we do the same with memory. Suppose we say. 35 00:04:09,020 --> 00:04:17,380 That's that. Ex. Is memory continuous with why? 36 00:04:17,380 --> 00:04:25,520 If either. X can remember Y's actions or. 37 00:04:25,520 --> 00:04:32,960 X can remember the actions of someone who is memory continuous with Y. 38 00:04:32,960 --> 00:04:39,620 So now what we have is that the general is memory continuous with the child 39 00:04:39,620 --> 00:04:43,130 because the general is memory continuous with the lieutenant and the lieutenant, 40 00:04:43,130 --> 00:04:50,070 his memory continuous with the child. So we get round Reid's problem by extending Locke's account. 41 00:04:50,070 --> 00:05:03,570 We don't make it rely just on what a single step memory we allow iterated memories to count as well. 42 00:05:03,570 --> 00:05:10,550 There's another advantage of this sort of approach, which is as follows. 43 00:05:10,550 --> 00:05:21,830 My continuity with myself yesterday. We're reluctant to think that that's anything to do with whether I can remember exactly what I did yesterday. 44 00:05:21,830 --> 00:05:29,300 I mean, suppose you go to a really good party and afterwards you can remember very little of what went on. 45 00:05:29,300 --> 00:05:38,710 That doesn't mean you're not the same person. Now. 46 00:05:38,710 --> 00:05:45,370 Suppose, on the other hand, do you imagine yourself through those hours? If you if you're calm. 47 00:05:45,370 --> 00:05:48,040 I realise this may be a question in those circumstances. 48 00:05:48,040 --> 00:05:58,480 But if your consciousness is continuous throughout the period, then you cannot each moment remember what happened in the immediately previous moment. 49 00:05:58,480 --> 00:06:04,810 You have it have, as it were, a continuity of experience and the ancestral relation. 50 00:06:04,810 --> 00:06:08,880 Let you build that right through the day. So you don't lose any. 51 00:06:08,880 --> 00:06:15,970 You don't have to say that at eleven o'clock in the evening, you have to be able to remember what happened at nine o'clock in the morning. 52 00:06:15,970 --> 00:06:27,430 The continuity can come through the ancestral relation. But there are, of course, lots of problems remaining. 53 00:06:27,430 --> 00:06:37,790 One problem is so-called quasar memory. If you base personal identity on memory. 54 00:06:37,790 --> 00:06:42,830 The trouble with that is something only counts as a genuine memory if it concerns your own experiences. 55 00:06:42,830 --> 00:06:49,380 Suppose I wake up. With an apparent memory of your experiences. 56 00:06:49,380 --> 00:06:53,910 Very peculiar. But would we call that memory? No, we wouldn't. 57 00:06:53,910 --> 00:06:57,510 We'd say that isn't a genuine memory. Something's gone wrong. 58 00:06:57,510 --> 00:07:02,760 Goodness knows what. But that's not a genuine memory. OK. 59 00:07:02,760 --> 00:07:09,960 So straight off, we need to say that the what we are using as a criterion of personal identity is not genuine memory. 60 00:07:09,960 --> 00:07:12,570 It's apparent memory, quasar memory. 61 00:07:12,570 --> 00:07:18,090 If we say genuine memory, then that's just going to be circular because we're only going to count it as genuine memory. 62 00:07:18,090 --> 00:07:26,710 If the we have personal identity. Another problem. 63 00:07:26,710 --> 00:07:36,770 Sleep. Well, continuity of consciousness may do the job from morning until night. 64 00:07:36,770 --> 00:07:43,490 But what about when you go to sleep? Does your consciousness then switch off? 65 00:07:43,490 --> 00:07:45,590 Well, maybe you can get round that. 66 00:07:45,590 --> 00:07:58,700 Maybe you can say with Descartes that it's of the essence of your mind that it's always thinking, maybe sometimes thinking semi consciously. 67 00:07:58,700 --> 00:08:04,220 And maybe you're going to be able to build that into some account. You can see there's a difficulty there. 68 00:08:04,220 --> 00:08:09,000 We're not going to be able to rely on full consciousness in the way that Locke wanted to. 69 00:08:09,000 --> 00:08:14,890 But what about Koma? What if someone goes into a coma? 70 00:08:14,890 --> 00:08:23,230 Suppose for a time, brain activity ceases. We have every reason to think that there is no consciousness, whatever, over that period. 71 00:08:23,230 --> 00:08:29,950 But then it revives. Would we not want to say that it's the same person? 72 00:08:29,950 --> 00:08:39,090 Particularly if they continue to act in the same way they retain memories from before and so on? 73 00:08:39,090 --> 00:08:44,850 Well, this suggests that some element of BOTTOMLY or at least brain continuity, is desirable. 74 00:08:44,850 --> 00:08:49,240 It enables you to bridge over the gaps in these sorts of cases. 75 00:08:49,240 --> 00:08:54,890 If somebody had a really bad accident, the brain appeared to switch off for a time. 76 00:08:54,890 --> 00:09:02,000 But then switched on again and things continued more or less as normal. I'm sure we would want to say it's the same person. 77 00:09:02,000 --> 00:09:08,030 We do that because largely because it's the same physical body. 78 00:09:08,030 --> 00:09:13,700 And we assume that with the same physical body. Broadly, the same mind is there. 79 00:09:13,700 --> 00:09:17,750 It's like turning your computer off and turning it on again. It's still your computer. 80 00:09:17,750 --> 00:09:28,910 It's still got all the memories and software, etc. from before. And that might lead us to think that bodily identity is really the crucial thing. 81 00:09:28,910 --> 00:09:34,850 Consciousness doesn't matter so much. What matters most is the physical seat of consciousness. 82 00:09:34,850 --> 00:09:40,565 The thing that actually causes it.