1 00:00:10,450 --> 00:00:15,400 Okay. Now we're going to move on to Hume's theory of space and time. 2 00:00:16,590 --> 00:00:20,400 Where we'll see that the theory of abstract ideas plays quite a significant role. 3 00:00:25,560 --> 00:00:28,620 So the theory of space and time comes in. Book one, part two of the Treaties. 4 00:00:29,880 --> 00:00:32,040 Now this part is very often ignored. 5 00:00:32,730 --> 00:00:40,380 If you look at books on HUME, you will often find that no mention of this is made at all, or it's treated rather dismissively. 6 00:00:41,610 --> 00:00:45,270 I actually think that's probably fairly justified. 7 00:00:45,930 --> 00:00:51,960 But you will find plenty of HUME scholars who will argue the reverse, and I'll be referring to some of them. 8 00:00:54,720 --> 00:01:02,430 Now, what you seems to be doing in this part of the treatise is applying his theory of ideas to draw 9 00:01:02,430 --> 00:01:10,440 conclusions about the nature of both our ideas of space and time and of space and time themselves. 10 00:01:11,190 --> 00:01:14,640 Now, you might think that the former is reasonable enough. 11 00:01:15,180 --> 00:01:24,240 He's looking at our ideas, investigating them, drawing conclusions about how we conceive of space and time. 12 00:01:25,940 --> 00:01:29,720 What seems a little bit more puzzling is that in this part of the treatise, 13 00:01:29,870 --> 00:01:38,600 he seems often to be drawing conclusions that go beyond that, that talk about space and time in themselves independently of our ideas. 14 00:01:41,930 --> 00:01:48,889 So the burden if the first part of part two is to argue that space and time, 15 00:01:48,890 --> 00:01:53,630 both our ideas and space and time themselves, are not infinitely divisible. 16 00:01:55,780 --> 00:02:02,290 So in the very first section entitled of the Infinite, The Visibility of our Ideas of Space and Time. 17 00:02:03,580 --> 00:02:07,360 Now again we find humour saying that something is very obvious. 18 00:02:07,930 --> 00:02:17,020 It is evident from the plainest observation that the capacity of the mind is limited and can never attain a full and adequate conception of infinity. 19 00:02:17,890 --> 00:02:20,980 Okay. Well, that seems reasonable enough, right? 20 00:02:21,340 --> 00:02:29,770 Our minds aren't infinite. If you try to imagine something that's infinite, you try to imagine the infinite sequence of numbers. 21 00:02:31,460 --> 00:02:37,430 Or the infinite number of fractions or imagine infinitely dividing a line. 22 00:02:38,900 --> 00:02:48,050 We do give up pretty quickly. It follows that the idea which we form of any finite quantity is not infinitely divisible. 23 00:02:49,220 --> 00:02:53,300 We must ultimately therefore reach a minimum. 24 00:02:56,910 --> 00:03:00,900 Now notice that there's a little bit of a an assumption here. 25 00:03:02,870 --> 00:03:09,950 HUME seems to be assuming that because we cannot go on dividing our ideas infinitely, 26 00:03:10,820 --> 00:03:17,090 we must hit rock bottom, as it were, with a particular minimum size. 27 00:03:18,240 --> 00:03:23,010 It's not absolutely clear that that's the case. And one could imagine. 28 00:03:24,050 --> 00:03:28,730 Trying to divide up one's image of something. 29 00:03:29,780 --> 00:03:33,050 And succeeding to different extents on different occasions. 30 00:03:33,980 --> 00:03:38,510 Perhaps sometimes we tire. Sometimes we feel more acute. 31 00:03:39,080 --> 00:03:47,710 And so we're able to go farther. But HUME has an argument or an illustration to back this up. 32 00:03:49,170 --> 00:03:54,150 So here's what we're supposed to do. Imagine an ink spot drawn on a board. 33 00:03:55,350 --> 00:03:59,190 And imagine retreating from it further and further and further. 34 00:03:59,700 --> 00:04:06,770 So the ink spot gets smaller and smaller. Until you just stop seeing it, it disappears. 35 00:04:07,190 --> 00:04:10,850 Then go back just a tiny bit so you can just see it. 36 00:04:12,180 --> 00:04:16,140 That is the minimum visible quantity. 37 00:04:17,310 --> 00:04:26,440 So what you will see, HUME thinks, is a coloured point, a coloured extension list point, because it will be indivisible. 38 00:04:26,460 --> 00:04:33,420 It will just be a point. You won't be able to distinguish the left side from the right side of it, but you will just see that point. 39 00:04:34,700 --> 00:04:37,070 So what we have here is a kind of visual atom. 40 00:04:38,160 --> 00:04:46,830 And we will see that HUME uses this atomic theory of our perceptions to draw quite significant conclusions. 41 00:04:49,370 --> 00:04:56,030 Now. In a recent article in Human Studies, Rolf George has made what I think is a very interesting speculation. 42 00:04:59,510 --> 00:05:06,110 The severability principle we've already met, and we'll see later Hume's various applications of it. 43 00:05:07,290 --> 00:05:11,909 But an intriguing fact about Hume's philosophy is that the severability principle is 44 00:05:11,910 --> 00:05:18,600 not mentioned at all after the treatise in the inquiry concerning human understanding. 45 00:05:19,200 --> 00:05:24,830 It doesn't come up at all. Some people claim that it's there implicitly in certain of the arguments. 46 00:05:25,190 --> 00:05:33,040 Personally, I'm not convinced. But what's also interesting is that a number of other things seem to disappear from the inquiry, 47 00:05:33,520 --> 00:05:38,230 which at least seem to be connected quite closely with the severability principle. 48 00:05:39,190 --> 00:05:45,880 For example, HUME drops the simple, complex distinction, or at least he puts much, much less emphasis on it. 49 00:05:47,380 --> 00:05:53,530 And the distinction between simple and complex ideas seems to be very much wrapped up with 50 00:05:53,530 --> 00:06:00,280 the theory we're talking about now about the simple visual atoms and atoms of other senses. 51 00:06:02,290 --> 00:06:06,250 Likewise in the inquiry, we get almost no discussion of space and time. 52 00:06:06,850 --> 00:06:11,559 We get a little bit when he talks about the sceptical arguments and we get a little footnote where 53 00:06:11,560 --> 00:06:16,360 he refers to his theory of abstract ideas and suggests that might possibly provide a solution. 54 00:06:17,190 --> 00:06:26,140 That said, there's a bit of a mystery there. We don't really know why HUME left this stuff out of the inquiry to obvious theories. 55 00:06:26,470 --> 00:06:30,670 One He wanted to make the inquiry more simple and palatable. 56 00:06:31,620 --> 00:06:33,329 He was addressing a different audience, 57 00:06:33,330 --> 00:06:39,300 an audience who wouldn't be interested in all the intricacies of infinite visibility and his discussion of space and time. 58 00:06:39,780 --> 00:06:44,850 So he saw no need to put in the severability principle. 59 00:06:46,920 --> 00:06:51,690 Maybe. That's right. But an alternative explanation is that he'd lost confidence in it. 60 00:06:52,110 --> 00:06:57,480 And Rolf George speculates a particular reason why this might be so. 61 00:06:57,960 --> 00:07:04,620 So in 1738, James Durin published an essay upon distinct and indistinct vision. 62 00:07:06,080 --> 00:07:14,030 And Georgie's hypothesis is that this, as it were, awoke David HUME from his dogmatic slumbers. 63 00:07:15,290 --> 00:07:18,830 How could it do that? Well, here we have a line and here we have a dot. 64 00:07:19,250 --> 00:07:26,090 And you will notice that the dot is wider, a greater diameter than the line is across. 65 00:07:27,950 --> 00:07:36,260 Now, imagine retreating further and further away from that until the dot cannot be seen. 66 00:07:38,360 --> 00:07:41,360 Nevertheless, you will still be able to see the line. 67 00:07:42,290 --> 00:07:49,790 Now, that's an empirical claim. What James Durian was doing was making empirical investigations into human acuity. 68 00:07:50,770 --> 00:07:53,520 But you can see that's a little bit of a problem for him. 69 00:07:54,890 --> 00:08:02,810 If you think that there are minima in our visual field of a certain fixed size that as you go smaller and smaller, 70 00:08:02,810 --> 00:08:08,090 you hit a limit like a computer pixel, just like the pixel on a computer screen. 71 00:08:08,720 --> 00:08:11,780 You cannot represent any image which is smaller than that. 72 00:08:13,130 --> 00:08:21,140 Well, at the point when that dot has disappeared, there should be no pixels at all left representing the line. 73 00:08:21,470 --> 00:08:28,330 So the line should disappear too. But it doesn't. So as I say, that's an interesting speculation. 74 00:08:28,510 --> 00:08:31,810 We don't know whether it's true. But the dates are very suggestive. 75 00:08:32,470 --> 00:08:35,680 We have this investigation being published in 1738. 76 00:08:36,040 --> 00:08:48,310 The treatise was published in 1739, a highly plausible that HUME between then and 1748 came across this, and George gives relevant evidence. 77 00:09:02,450 --> 00:09:06,650 Okay. But let's now proceed and see what he does with his theory. 78 00:09:09,130 --> 00:09:12,430 Well, having established that there are these minima. 79 00:09:13,950 --> 00:09:18,060 HUME considers. Those. 80 00:09:18,870 --> 00:09:26,430 Now, if we hit a minimum, if we actually think of a minimum possible point, it's extinction less. 81 00:09:27,000 --> 00:09:30,960 You cannot distinguish the left from the right. It's as small as anything could be. 82 00:09:33,070 --> 00:09:40,450 It follows that nothing can be more my Newt than some ideas which we form in the fantasy that the fancy remember is another name for the imagination. 83 00:09:41,700 --> 00:09:48,000 And images which appear to the senses, since these are ideas and images perfectly simple and indivisible. 84 00:09:49,320 --> 00:09:56,000 The only defect of our senses is that they give us disproportionate images of things and represent as my Newton unkempt. 85 00:09:56,520 --> 00:09:59,730 What is really great and composed of a vast number of parts. 86 00:10:00,690 --> 00:10:11,760 So take that dot that we've drawn on a board and maybe it's quite big, but we go further and further and further away until we can only just see it. 87 00:10:12,540 --> 00:10:16,800 And at that point it looks to us completely simple and on compounded. 88 00:10:17,280 --> 00:10:28,830 We just see the dot. Now we might therefore have the erroneously draw the conclusion that the thing itself that we're seeing is totally simple. 89 00:10:30,420 --> 00:10:34,770 But what we can do at that point is pull out our binoculars or our telescope and take a look. 90 00:10:34,770 --> 00:10:40,350 And we see, oh, it's bigger. So it's clear that there are a lot of light rays coming. 91 00:10:41,040 --> 00:10:44,460 And if we use instruments, we can see the thing in more detail. 92 00:10:44,700 --> 00:10:56,730 It ceases to be so simple. But what HUME wants to say is that that simple idea that we get correctly represents the smallest part of anything. 93 00:10:57,640 --> 00:11:16,200 Nothing can be smaller than that. So we get a famous image of a flea from Hooke's Micrographia, 1665, and HUME is clearly alluding to this. 94 00:11:17,280 --> 00:11:22,169 This, however, is certain that we can form ideas which shall be no greater than the smallest 95 00:11:22,170 --> 00:11:27,000 atom of the animal spirits of an insect a thousand times less than a mite. 96 00:11:27,600 --> 00:11:30,120 The animal spirits think of what goes through the nerves, 97 00:11:31,380 --> 00:11:37,080 and we ought rather to conclude that the difficulty lies in enlarging our conception so much as 98 00:11:37,080 --> 00:11:43,830 to form a just notion of a mite or even of an insect a thousand times less than a might for. 99 00:11:43,830 --> 00:11:50,070 In order to form a just notion of these animals, we must have a distinct idea representing every part of them. 100 00:11:51,900 --> 00:11:52,980 So what's going on here? 101 00:11:53,010 --> 00:12:02,160 You might think that, you know, when we look at something from a distance, as it were, we're making an error in seeing the thing as simple. 102 00:12:02,470 --> 00:12:10,920 Our idea as it were is misrepresenting it. And him saying, we think thinking that way around it is the wrong way, actually. 103 00:12:11,130 --> 00:12:19,020 We can form ideas which are adequate to the tiny parts of things because our ideas are pure and simple. 104 00:12:19,290 --> 00:12:25,320 They just aren't compounded. So they form an adequate idea of the very smallest parts of anything. 105 00:12:25,980 --> 00:12:30,450 What's actually difficult is forming an idea adequate to a whole might. 106 00:12:30,840 --> 00:12:34,020 That's vastly complex. Or even a creature. 107 00:12:34,020 --> 00:12:41,220 A thousand. Part of that sort. Thousandth part of a mind. Okay. 108 00:12:42,150 --> 00:12:45,210 So HUME has drawn here an important conclusion, 109 00:12:45,660 --> 00:12:56,700 and it's one that he's going to use now to conclude about space and time in themselves rather than just about our ideas. 110 00:12:57,450 --> 00:12:59,790 So we get that right at the beginning of treatise one, two, two. 111 00:13:01,830 --> 00:13:10,680 Wherever ideas are adequate representations of objects, the relations, contradictions and agreements of the ideas are all applicable to the objects. 112 00:13:11,460 --> 00:13:19,700 Okay, that seems reasonable. If our ideas are faithful representations of the way objects are. 113 00:13:20,950 --> 00:13:28,450 Then inevitably any conclusions that we draw from the ideas will be applicable to the objects. 114 00:13:28,450 --> 00:13:32,080 And I realise you're all wondering where the handout for this is. 115 00:13:32,290 --> 00:13:36,279 It'll come next week with stuff for next time. 116 00:13:36,280 --> 00:13:41,870 Because what didn't make up a complete end up. Okay. 117 00:13:41,870 --> 00:13:49,310 So fair enough. If we've got adequate ideas, the ideas, as I say, faithfully represent what they are ideas of. 118 00:13:49,850 --> 00:13:53,240 Then in reasoning about the ideas and drawing conclusions about those, 119 00:13:53,390 --> 00:13:59,570 those conclusions will inevitably follow to the things that the ideas represent. 120 00:14:00,770 --> 00:14:03,950 But here comes the crucial claim, the one he's been arguing for. 121 00:14:04,640 --> 00:14:09,350 But our ideas are adequate representations of the most mind parts of extension. 122 00:14:10,100 --> 00:14:14,450 And through whatever divisions and subdivisions we may suppose these parts to be arrived at. 123 00:14:14,960 --> 00:14:18,920 They can never become inferior to some ideas which we form. 124 00:14:19,400 --> 00:14:26,810 So the ideas are so simple, so un compounded that no part of extension can possibly be less than those. 125 00:14:27,710 --> 00:14:33,020 The plain consequences that whatever appears impossible and contradictory upon the comparison of 126 00:14:33,200 --> 00:14:38,750 these ideas must be really impossible and contradictory without any farther excuse or evasion. 127 00:14:40,380 --> 00:14:47,790 Now notice that HUME here is not using what might seem seem to be his conceive ability principle. 128 00:14:48,570 --> 00:14:53,280 He's arguing from inconceivable bility to impossibility. 129 00:14:54,180 --> 00:14:59,069 That's different from arguing from conceive ability to possibility. 130 00:14:59,070 --> 00:15:04,170 We saw the conceived policy principle last time. We'll be seeing lots more of the conceive ability principle. 131 00:15:04,620 --> 00:15:10,050 HUME thinks quite generally that to conceive of something distinctly. 132 00:15:11,610 --> 00:15:16,470 Implies its possibility. You cannot distinctly conceive of something that's impossible. 133 00:15:17,160 --> 00:15:25,170 Okay, so conceive ability implies possibility. But here he's saying that inconceivable bility implies impossibility. 134 00:15:26,160 --> 00:15:31,350 But he only wants to say that that applies where ideas are adequate. 135 00:15:32,500 --> 00:15:38,650 Now that's quite important. Remember humans and empiricist. He thinks our ideas are derived from impressions. 136 00:15:39,400 --> 00:15:42,910 He thinks, for example, that a blind man has no visual ideas. 137 00:15:44,080 --> 00:15:49,570 So he surely doesn't want to say that. Inconceivable, as he quite generally implies, impossibility. 138 00:15:49,750 --> 00:15:53,980 There may be all sorts of things which we cannot conceive because we don't have the ideas. 139 00:15:55,160 --> 00:16:02,900 And he said that our minds are finite. There may be all sorts of things that we can't conceive of because we're just not capable of it. 140 00:16:03,620 --> 00:16:06,680 We don't want to conclude, in general, that that implies impossibility. 141 00:16:07,490 --> 00:16:10,400 But when our ideas are adequate, that's a different matter. 142 00:16:14,900 --> 00:16:21,410 So he's already said that our ideas are adequate representations of the most minor parts of extension. 143 00:16:22,250 --> 00:16:29,600 We've seen that our ideas are not infinitely divisible and it follows that the same is true of space. 144 00:16:31,370 --> 00:16:38,180 I first take the least idea I can form of the part of extension and being certain that there is nothing more my newt than this idea. 145 00:16:38,510 --> 00:16:43,340 I conclude that whatever I discover by its means must be a real quality of extension. 146 00:16:44,510 --> 00:16:47,720 I then repeat this idea once, twice, thrice. 147 00:16:47,870 --> 00:16:55,479 So imagine that tiny little atomic idea. And now put another one next to it and another one next to that. 148 00:16:55,480 --> 00:16:59,530 And if it helps, think of them as differently coloured. You start off with a blue dot. 149 00:17:00,430 --> 00:17:08,410 Remember, it's extension lists. You can't distinguish its parts. But now you put a red dot next to it, maybe a yellow dot next to that. 150 00:17:09,720 --> 00:17:16,710 And what you do now is build up extension. The idea of extension comes to you as soon as you've got more than one of these. 151 00:17:23,020 --> 00:17:27,850 So each of our minimal ideas is indivisible and therefore not extended. 152 00:17:28,360 --> 00:17:32,080 But as soon as you put two together, you've got the minutia part of extension. 153 00:17:32,350 --> 00:17:35,710 Add another one, you've got a bit more extension. Add another one. 154 00:17:35,920 --> 00:17:39,190 You've got more. Carry on to infinity. 155 00:17:39,190 --> 00:17:43,210 Where do you get? Well, you're going to have an infinitely large extension. No way round it. 156 00:17:44,440 --> 00:17:49,120 Although each individual, indivisible atom, as it were, is unexpended. 157 00:17:49,390 --> 00:17:54,460 As soon as you put lots of them together, you get a finite extension. 158 00:17:54,970 --> 00:17:58,450 If you put an infinite number together, you will get an infinite extension. 159 00:18:00,200 --> 00:18:08,090 So he goes as far as saying that the idea of an infinite number of paths is the same idea with that of an infinite extension. 160 00:18:10,490 --> 00:18:14,760 So he's proved. To his satisfaction. 161 00:18:14,760 --> 00:18:24,180 At any rate, that space is not infinitely divisible because we've got these little ideas that are adequate to the minimalist parts of space. 162 00:18:25,290 --> 00:18:34,379 And if space were infinitely divisible, then you'd have to be able to have an infinite number of these tiny parts within a finite amount of space. 163 00:18:34,380 --> 00:18:41,190 But you can't, because as soon as you get an infinite number of these little atoms, you get an infinite extension. 164 00:18:44,380 --> 00:18:52,790 Now. If you're familiar at all with mathematics, an objection is likely to come to your mind. 165 00:18:53,900 --> 00:18:59,450 Imagine something that's finite, extended. Imagine dividing that extension into and taking half of it. 166 00:18:59,600 --> 00:19:04,340 Then divide that in two and take half. Divide that in two and take half and go on and on and on and on and on. 167 00:19:04,850 --> 00:19:07,850 You start with a half, then a quarter, then an 1860. 168 00:19:08,540 --> 00:19:14,170 On and on and on. Without stopping, apparently. So what's wrong with that? 169 00:19:14,200 --> 00:19:21,089 Why can't you divide things infinitely? Well, Jim actually addresses this objection. 170 00:19:21,090 --> 00:19:25,590 In a footnote, he distinguishes between proportional and adequate parts. 171 00:19:26,190 --> 00:19:31,800 It's a proportional part where you're dividing up again and again and again like this, adequate parts, all of equal size. 172 00:19:33,820 --> 00:19:40,030 And he just seems rather dogmatically to say, Well, that doesn't deal with my argument. 173 00:19:41,340 --> 00:19:47,460 Because nothing I've prove nothing can be inferior to those main parts we conceive. 174 00:19:47,610 --> 00:19:51,240 When I think of this idea of a simple, nothing can be smaller than that. 175 00:19:51,690 --> 00:19:54,750 So divide up as much as you like. You cannot get smaller than that. 176 00:19:55,590 --> 00:20:00,809 And if you can't get smaller than that, then an infinite number of those is going to give you an infinite extension. 177 00:20:00,810 --> 00:20:14,540 So there you are. My argument stands. Later into the intersection, HUME again comes back and deals with a potential mathematical argument. 178 00:20:16,220 --> 00:20:24,020 So there are various mathematical arguments that seem to tell in favour of infinite visibility that seem to try to prove it. 179 00:20:24,950 --> 00:20:28,760 And HUME says these can't be right. Now, he is appealing to the conceive ability principle. 180 00:20:29,090 --> 00:20:34,400 He's saying, I have this notion of space made up of all these little atoms. 181 00:20:35,090 --> 00:20:38,420 That's a conceivable picture of the way space could be. 182 00:20:40,040 --> 00:20:45,950 Since it's conceivable, it's possible. So any attempted proof that it's impossible must be fallacious. 183 00:20:48,410 --> 00:20:55,580 So he's attacking the mathematical objection to his own view and he's attacking himself. 184 00:20:55,820 --> 00:21:00,920 The argument of mathematicians that he's claimed as a positive proof of infinite visibility. 185 00:21:02,530 --> 00:21:06,430 Now, these arguments don't seem to be. 186 00:21:07,560 --> 00:21:16,620 Ideal. Particularly his argument against infinite visibility, against proportional parts. 187 00:21:19,540 --> 00:21:27,820 Because when he says My idea is as simple as can be, this atomic idea of a visual atom. 188 00:21:28,980 --> 00:21:34,050 Must correctly represent the smallest parts of space because nothing could possibly be smaller. 189 00:21:35,480 --> 00:21:40,220 Therefore, when you finally get down to the ultimate bits of space, they're going to be simple. 190 00:21:40,310 --> 00:21:43,370 My idea is simple. Therefore, the two must match. 191 00:21:43,940 --> 00:21:52,320 That must be an adequate idea. The obvious response is to say, well, I'm sorry, who if space is infinitely divisible? 192 00:21:52,350 --> 00:21:55,560 You never do. Get down to an ultimately simple part. 193 00:21:56,860 --> 00:22:02,860 So I went in claiming that the ultimate parts of space must match with this idea. 194 00:22:02,890 --> 00:22:08,740 You're begging the question you're taking for granted that you do actually get two ultimate simples. 195 00:22:09,760 --> 00:22:12,910 And that's just assuming that space isn't infinitely divisible. 196 00:22:15,200 --> 00:22:20,600 So there's a bit of a puzzle here. I mean, humans generally are pretty acute philosopher, as I've said, 197 00:22:20,660 --> 00:22:26,030 but one part two is probably, well, almost certainly the weakest part of treatise. 198 00:22:26,030 --> 00:22:35,660 But what? The arguments aren't that great. And maybe HUME just imagined himself to be better at mathematics than he really was later in life. 199 00:22:35,990 --> 00:22:44,210 He did actually produce a treatise on geometry, and he was persuaded by Lord Stanhope, a noted mathematician, not to publish it. 200 00:22:45,590 --> 00:22:47,360 Sadly, it disappeared without trace. 201 00:22:47,360 --> 00:22:53,899 It'd be great if it turned up at some point, but at any rate, when he wrote the treatise, he seems pretty confident, doesn't it? 202 00:22:53,900 --> 00:22:57,110 Is evident this is absolutely clear, etc. 203 00:22:59,520 --> 00:23:05,640 So is something going on that brought it about that he didn't see the problems that we see in his arguments? 204 00:23:06,180 --> 00:23:13,070 Well, here we reduced really to speculation. Tom Holden, a book published in 2004. 205 00:23:13,550 --> 00:23:17,480 He suggests that HUME is presupposing an actual part's metaphysic, 206 00:23:17,930 --> 00:23:23,750 whereby anything that is divisible must in advance consist of the actual parts into which it is divided. 207 00:23:24,530 --> 00:23:33,740 So contrast to different possible accounts of visibility, you've got the Aristotelian idea of potential infinities. 208 00:23:34,070 --> 00:23:37,430 So suppose I take an extension, divide it up. Divide that again. 209 00:23:37,430 --> 00:23:44,330 Again and again and again. Like, however much I divide it, I can go on dividing further. 210 00:23:45,230 --> 00:23:51,040 So in that sense, there's a potential infinity. It's like saying, give me any number. 211 00:23:51,050 --> 00:23:54,680 I can always add one. You can always go further. 212 00:23:54,770 --> 00:24:00,530 So there's a potential infinity. But that's different from saying that there's an actual infinity. 213 00:24:01,280 --> 00:24:08,270 You can say that the the line is potentially divisible without claiming that it is already divided into parts, 214 00:24:08,390 --> 00:24:12,650 that those separate parts already exist, as it were, prior to the division. 215 00:24:13,940 --> 00:24:21,950 But Tom argues that at the time the actual part, metaphysic was very strongly in the air. 216 00:24:23,030 --> 00:24:27,200 The thought that if some things divisible, the parts already have to be there. 217 00:24:27,200 --> 00:24:38,149 They have to exist prior to the division. Now that suggestion is somewhat supported by an argument that HUME uses in treaties. 218 00:24:38,150 --> 00:24:40,700 One, two, two, three. He borrows it from Nicholas. 219 00:24:41,090 --> 00:24:48,410 The militia is evident that existence in itself belongs only to unity and is never applicable to number. 220 00:24:48,680 --> 00:24:51,860 But on account of the unities of which the number is composed, 221 00:24:52,670 --> 00:24:58,490 it is therefore utterly absurd to suppose any number to exist and yet deny the existence of unities. 222 00:24:59,240 --> 00:25:01,880 And as extension is always a number and so on. 223 00:25:02,300 --> 00:25:09,590 The thought is if a group of people exist, they exist only in virtue of the existence of each one of them. 224 00:25:10,500 --> 00:25:18,300 Take any number of things. The ultimate existence are always the unities of which the group is composed. 225 00:25:19,530 --> 00:25:25,020 Now apply that to an extension. The thought would be that unless there are ultimate parts of extension. 226 00:25:26,280 --> 00:25:32,250 Nothing exists. So if if if you always can divide further, you never hit the ground. 227 00:25:32,970 --> 00:25:43,430 Then ultimately, metaphysically, there's nothing. Another possible account of what's going on is due to Don Baxter. 228 00:25:44,030 --> 00:25:49,790 He's written an article in the Cambridge Companion to HUME quite recent. 229 00:25:51,010 --> 00:25:55,030 And he suggests that HUME is pursuing a somewhat Kantian agenda. 230 00:25:55,270 --> 00:26:00,400 So what Immanuel Kant wanted to do was to say that our knowledge of space and time, 231 00:26:00,970 --> 00:26:08,170 our knowledge of space and time in the phenomenal world, in the world that we experience, not in the world as it is in itself. 232 00:26:09,850 --> 00:26:10,240 And. 233 00:26:11,210 --> 00:26:20,870 So Baxter suggestion is that Hume's aim is to find out about objects as they appear to us, by examination of the ideas that we use to represent them. 234 00:26:21,980 --> 00:26:27,680 So it's less ambitious. The thought is Hume's concern is with space and time. 235 00:26:27,890 --> 00:26:38,340 Within, as it were, the experienced manifold. And within that realm, the limits of space and time are given by the limits of our ideas. 236 00:26:40,020 --> 00:26:43,290 I'm not persuaded, but it's an interesting suggestion. 237 00:26:47,600 --> 00:26:54,890 Finally notice that HUME draws the same conclusions about time that he draws about space. 238 00:26:55,550 --> 00:27:01,640 All this reasoning, he says, takes place with regard to time, and he adds an extra argument. 239 00:27:01,730 --> 00:27:05,030 It's the essence of temporal moments to be successive. 240 00:27:05,300 --> 00:27:08,810 Time is of its nature, successive in a way that space isn't. 241 00:27:09,860 --> 00:27:14,780 So if time were infinitely divisible, you'd get coexisting moments. 242 00:27:14,780 --> 00:27:17,960 And that's not possible. So time can't be infinitely divisible. 243 00:27:18,890 --> 00:27:24,260 And then as soon as you think of motion something moving in time through space, 244 00:27:24,500 --> 00:27:32,780 you can see that if infinite visibility of time is impossible, infinite the visibility of space must be as well. 245 00:27:33,680 --> 00:27:38,090 Okay, we'll continue next time with a little bit more on space and time. 246 00:27:38,390 --> 00:27:44,960 And then we will be getting on to book one, part three, which is the most important part of the entire treatise. 247 00:27:45,560 --> 00:27:46,070 See you then.