1 00:00:01,000 --> 00:00:12,000 So today, we've got Dr. Mackenzie, Graham. Mackenzie is a senior research fellow at the centre and the welcomes in the ethics and Humanities. 2 00:00:12,000 --> 00:00:20,970 And of course, he's also a Uehiro alumni. He's currently part of the National Consortium of Intelligent Medical Imaging, 3 00:00:20,970 --> 00:00:27,360 investigating ethical issues arising from the collection, storage and sharing of digitised medical images. 4 00:00:27,360 --> 00:00:36,000 And that project is aiming to facilitate the ethical integration of A.I. enhanced clinical imaging into medical practise. 5 00:00:36,000 --> 00:00:41,000 And that project is still in its early stages. And so we're not going to hear about that now. 6 00:00:41,000 --> 00:00:47,000 Keep in mind, in case you were interested in that kind of thing, Mackenzie is working on that. 7 00:00:47,000 --> 00:00:53,000 But today we're going to hear about choosing now for later, precedent, 8 00:00:53,000 --> 00:01:00,000 autonomy and problem of surrogate decision making after severe brain injury. Take it away 9 00:01:00,000 --> 00:01:05,010 Mackenzie. Great. OK. Thanks, Dad. Yeah. 10 00:01:05,010 --> 00:01:15,540 So my name's Mackenzie. So today I'm going to talk a little bit about a group of patients with disorders of consciousness. 11 00:01:15,540 --> 00:01:21,000 So it's a if any of you have heard me speak before, you've probably heard a little bit about these patients. 12 00:01:21,000 --> 00:01:27,600 Kind of my previous research before I started doing stuff with AI was on these patients 13 00:01:27,600 --> 00:01:32,670 and I was interested in questions of understanding well-being in these patients. 14 00:01:32,670 --> 00:01:39,510 So this is a little bit different kind of project, which is sort of in its middle stages. 15 00:01:39,510 --> 00:01:48,120 We'll call it. So I'm interested in how we are to make decisions on behalf of these patients in kind of the weeks, 16 00:01:48,120 --> 00:01:51,090 the days, weeks and months just after their injury. 17 00:01:51,090 --> 00:01:57,780 So there's kind of a standard way that we approach these sorts of problems, which I'll talk about can be early going. 18 00:01:57,780 --> 00:02:05,000 And then I'll explain why. I think that is the standard approach has some problems, especially as it pertains to patients like this, 19 00:02:05,000 --> 00:02:11,670 I'll use them as kind of a heated theme to illustrate what I take to be some weaknesses in the standard view. 20 00:02:11,670 --> 00:02:16,910 And then I'll try and sketch out a bit of a way forward for how. 21 00:02:16,910 --> 00:02:24,890 How we can make decisions on behalf of these patients. So we'll get started with a case. 22 00:02:24,890 --> 00:02:30,000 That's a good place to start. OK, so Frieda is a 32 year old female. 23 00:02:30,000 --> 00:02:36,000 She suffered a severe traumatic brain injury when she was struck by a motor vehicle while riding a bicycle. 24 00:02:36,000 --> 00:02:44,000 So she's rushed to the hospital. And her condition is stabilised by emergency physician, but she remains in a coma for about five days. 25 00:02:44,000 --> 00:02:48,950 You see, this is clearly a pre COVID kind of ICU. 26 00:02:48,950 --> 00:02:57,410 So her husband is acting as her surrogate decision maker and he's informed by her neurologist that her prognosis is uncertain. 27 00:02:57,410 --> 00:03:04,310 But the husband elects to continue life sustaining treatment because we are still kind of in the early going. 28 00:03:04,310 --> 00:03:12,740 So after about two months, Freeda has emerged from a coma. And unfortunately, she's diagnosed as having unresponsive wakefulness syndrome. 29 00:03:12,740 --> 00:03:15,000 This is also referred to as a vegetative state. 30 00:03:15,000 --> 00:03:21,890 So Frieda's not showing any evidence of awareness of herself or her environment during a bedside examination. 31 00:03:21,890 --> 00:03:25,790 So when doctors ask her to sort of follow up penlight with her, 32 00:03:25,790 --> 00:03:31,220 whether eyes or wiggle her toes or squeeze her fingers to command, she's not able to do any of this. 33 00:03:31,220 --> 00:03:37,340 So she's able to sort of move reflexively, but she's not able to do any kind of voluntary movement. 34 00:03:37,340 --> 00:03:42,000 She doesn't appear to understand language or anything like that. 35 00:03:42,000 --> 00:03:49,000 However, an EEG has detected a P300 signal in response to a recording of her voice. 36 00:03:49,000 --> 00:03:55,000 when you play recording of her voice beside her, we see a little a little bit of a brain signal. 37 00:03:55,000 --> 00:04:00,280 And this in the past is found to be predictive of recovery in our post-traumatic vegetative state. 38 00:04:00,280 --> 00:04:06,000 So there's some indication that maybe she'll make a recovery. But other than that, things aren't looking very good. 39 00:04:06,000 --> 00:04:15,970 So at this stage, after her injury, so this is sort of two months after her accident, it remains unclear to what extent Frieda might actually recover. 40 00:04:15,970 --> 00:04:22,180 So on the one hand, her husband believes that she wouldn't want to continue living in a severely disabled state like this. 41 00:04:22,180 --> 00:04:27,670 And he thinks this because she often talked about her grandmother's decline in the later 42 00:04:27,670 --> 00:04:35,000 stages of dementia and how she wouldn't want to live in a severely disabled state like this. 43 00:04:35,000 --> 00:04:40,120 So the husband thinks well actually maybe the best thing to do for her is to withdraw her from treatment. 44 00:04:40,120 --> 00:04:45,000 Her parents, on the other hand, believe that there's a reasonable chance of a meaningful recovery even still, 45 00:04:45,000 --> 00:04:52,690 and that with the right support Frieda could have an acceptable quality of life, even in a pretty severely disabled state. 46 00:04:52,690 --> 00:04:58,360 However, no one is really sure how to proceed. 47 00:04:58,360 --> 00:05:04,330 So sadly, this is, I think, a pretty indicative case for these kinds of patients. 48 00:05:04,330 --> 00:05:10,000 Things are often very uncertain for quite a long time until the patient sort of declares themselves. 49 00:05:10,000 --> 00:05:13,000 You might say. 50 00:05:13,000 --> 00:05:20,170 So It might take weeks, weeks or months, several months before we really get a clear sense of what we can expect from the patient in terms of recovery. 51 00:05:20,170 --> 00:05:27,380 But families have to make very difficult decisions on the basis of not a lot of evidence. 52 00:05:27,380 --> 00:05:32,440 And obviously, because these are oftentimes life or death decisions can be very difficult. 53 00:05:32,440 --> 00:05:34,930 So these are the kinds of patients I want to talk about today. 54 00:05:34,930 --> 00:05:41,760 But first, we'll do a little bit of background in disorders of consciousness just to kind of sit this here. 55 00:05:41,760 --> 00:05:53,130 So this is just kind of a basic diagram of how different disorders of consciousness can kind of be arranged along these three sorts of scales. 56 00:05:53,130 --> 00:05:57,000 So it's a collection of syndromes, disorders of consciousness that are kind of transitory. 57 00:05:57,000 --> 00:06:02,580 So typically you move from whom might need to [inaudible] And then make a full recovery. 58 00:06:02,580 --> 00:06:07,290 Not usually. But when you do make a full recovery, kind of move through these stages. 59 00:06:07,290 --> 00:06:12,000 And after about four weeks, it's considered a prolonged disorder of consciousness. 60 00:06:12,000 --> 00:06:19,560 So the way we diagnose these disorders is that usually with a bedside behavioural tests. 61 00:06:19,560 --> 00:06:25,380 So we'll ask a patient to follow commands. So we'll say it's you can not understand what I'm saying. 62 00:06:25,380 --> 00:06:30,450 Wiggle your wiggle your toes or move your move your fingers. 63 00:06:30,450 --> 00:06:34,470 We'll ask you asking you turn to turn your head in a certain way or things like that. 64 00:06:34,470 --> 00:06:42,150 So patients in a coma down here in the bottom left of the laser pointer right here in a coma. 65 00:06:42,150 --> 00:06:46,140 You can see are not aware and they're not awake and they don't move. 66 00:06:46,140 --> 00:06:51,000 So these are patients eyes are closed, completely unaware of what's going on around them. 67 00:06:51,000 --> 00:06:57,000 So they're kind of at zero on the wakefulness scale. The awareness scale and the motor behaviour scale. VS patients. 68 00:06:57,000 --> 00:07:02,040 So this is the state that we think Frieda from the example is in. 69 00:07:02,040 --> 00:07:08,310 She is awake, so her eyes are open and these patients go through kind of sleeping, waking cycles. 70 00:07:08,310 --> 00:07:15,090 But they're not aware of anything that's going on around them. So they're kind of at zero in the awareness scale. 71 00:07:15,090 --> 00:07:18,000 And also, they don't they don't move kind of voluntarily. 72 00:07:18,000 --> 00:07:26,700 So we will sometimes see kind of reflexive movements from these patients, but they don't exhibit sort of voluntary motor behaviour. 73 00:07:26,700 --> 00:07:34,000 In about 2002, this was first this condition was first discovered and kind of in the 1970s. 74 00:07:34,000 --> 00:07:39,000 And then in about 2002, physicians started distinguishing between VS patients and MCS patients. 75 00:07:39,000 --> 00:07:45,810 So these are patients you can see are also awake and they go through intermittent kind of stages of awareness. 76 00:07:45,810 --> 00:07:53,790 So sometimes they're able to follow commands and sometimes they're able to, as you can see, also move volitionally, but sometimes they can't. 77 00:07:53,790 --> 00:07:57,000 It kind of depends on when the assessment takes place. 78 00:07:57,000 --> 00:08:07,270 If we're able to diagnose someone as MCS, so MC.S. plus and, M.CS. minus relates to whether the patient can actually communicate or not. 79 00:08:07,270 --> 00:08:12,270 And then we see up at the very top is full consciousness. So like you and I, we're fully awake. 80 00:08:12,270 --> 00:08:16,320 We're fully aware and capable of volitional motor behaviour. 81 00:08:16,320 --> 00:08:21,000 So the patients I'm going to talk about today are these patients, CND patients. 82 00:08:21,000 --> 00:08:30,000 So only recently have these patients even begun to be recognised because it's very difficult to tell the difference between a CND patient and a VS 83 00:08:30,000 --> 00:08:35,000 patient. So these patients are awake. And as it turns out, they are aware. 84 00:08:35,000 --> 00:08:38,070 But because they don't exhibit any motor behaviour, 85 00:08:38,070 --> 00:08:46,000 it's very difficult to tell the difference between these two using only kind of behavioural scale. 86 00:08:46,000 --> 00:08:52,000 So, as they say, it's very difficult to to diagnose kind of NCS or CND. 87 00:08:52,000 --> 00:08:56,000 So about 40 percent of the time someone is diagnosed as being in a VS. 88 00:08:56,000 --> 00:09:01,000 This is a misdiagnosis. So we do the behavioural assessment. 89 00:09:01,000 --> 00:09:05,640 We think OK so this patient's totally not responsive if we reassess them. 90 00:09:05,640 --> 00:09:12,000 You know, a few days later, sometimes we end up getting them at a period where they're a little bit more aware. 91 00:09:12,000 --> 00:09:21,000 And then we're able to see that actually this patient is a NCS. So it's quite difficult to to get this right. 92 00:09:21,000 --> 00:09:26,040 So right. So this is usually done on the basis of a bed side assessment. 93 00:09:26,040 --> 00:09:30,000 And as I say, these are these are not perfect measures, 94 00:09:30,000 --> 00:09:40,340 but even amongst patients that are repeatedly diagnosed as being in the V.S. using these behavioural scales, 95 00:09:40,340 --> 00:09:44,000 studies have shown over the last decade or so, 10, 96 00:09:44,000 --> 00:09:52,310 15 years, have shown that about 15 percent, actually probably about 15 to 17 percent now of patients who repeatedly satisfy all of 97 00:09:52,310 --> 00:09:58,000 the diagnostic diagnostic criteria for being in a vegetative state are actually aware. 98 00:09:58,000 --> 00:10:09,320 So are actually CMD we would now call them. So the first kind of landmark study that showed this was in 2006 by Adrian Owen and colleagues. 99 00:10:09,320 --> 00:10:14,000 This was at Cambridge University. Now he's at the University of Western Ontario. 100 00:10:14,000 --> 00:10:25,000 So for those of you who are familiar with this research, basically what what they did was they put these patients in a FMRI scanner. 101 00:10:25,000 --> 00:10:35,000 So these patients had been repeatedly diagnosed as VS. They were put in an F MRI scanner and asked to imagine performing certain tasks. 102 00:10:35,000 --> 00:10:40,530 when instructed to do so. So here we can see kind of. 103 00:10:40,530 --> 00:10:48,530 An image of a healthy person's brain. Had sort of the normal shape, and this is one of the patients that suffered a traumatic brain injury. 104 00:10:48,530 --> 00:10:52,830 You can see there where the trauma occurred. 105 00:10:52,830 --> 00:10:59,790 So what they were asked to do was once they were in the in the scanner, asked to imagine playing tennis when they heard the word imagine. 106 00:10:59,790 --> 00:11:07,290 So we had healthy controls. When we ask someone to imagine playing tennis, we see activation the supplementary motor area right here. 107 00:11:07,290 --> 00:11:11,970 And if we if a patient was truly unconscious, we would expect to see nothing. 108 00:11:11,970 --> 00:11:19,650 But in about 50 percent of patients, as it turns out, we see very similar activation to an healthy participant. 109 00:11:19,650 --> 00:11:25,260 So they would ask them to imagine playing tennis for about 30 seconds. So you can do this for yourself. 110 00:11:25,260 --> 00:11:30,000 It requires a fair amount of focus to kind of sustain your attention on this particular task for that amount of time. 111 00:11:30,000 --> 00:11:35,000 So we would ask them to play. Imagine playing tennis for 30 seconds. Then they relax. 112 00:11:35,000 --> 00:11:42,480 And then the activation will go away. And they'd ask for then to imagine to play tennis again, the brain light up again. 113 00:11:42,480 --> 00:11:46,590 Tell them to relax. So they would do this kind of blocks of five. 114 00:11:46,590 --> 00:11:52,740 So the odds of this happening sort of just by chance, I would say, were slim to none. 115 00:11:52,740 --> 00:11:59,550 Especially with sort of repeat repeat scanning. So they in addition to the tennis task, 116 00:11:59,550 --> 00:12:07,290 they also ask them to imagine walking around a familiar room in their house or sort of walking around the streets of their neighbourhood. 117 00:12:07,290 --> 00:12:11,520 And this activates a whole network of brain areas in a healthy control. 118 00:12:11,520 --> 00:12:19,320 As we can see, a similar network within some patients that are diagnosis vegetated. 119 00:12:19,320 --> 00:12:23,850 So patients fitting this profile so behaviourally nonresponsive, 120 00:12:23,850 --> 00:12:29,370 yet able to demonstrate evidence of awareness and command following are called cognitive. 121 00:12:29,370 --> 00:12:36,660 That are said to have cognitive motive association. So they're aware, but they don't display any kind of motor behaviour. 122 00:12:36,660 --> 00:12:41,130 So these patients can encompass sort of a wide range of capacities. 123 00:12:41,130 --> 00:12:48,840 We know that they possess certain cognitive capacities just as an inference from what it would take to do kind of mental imagery task. 124 00:12:48,840 --> 00:12:54,150 So we know that they can understand language. We know that they're capable of sustaining their attention certain way. 125 00:12:54,150 --> 00:13:00,090 We know they have some degree of working memory because you remember the instructions and then carry them out. 126 00:13:00,090 --> 00:13:06,000 They have some degree of response selection so they can decide what to think about if you ask them to imagine playing tennis. 127 00:13:06,000 --> 00:13:11,190 They could have imagined something else, but they chose to imagine playing tennis. And a subset of patients. 128 00:13:11,190 --> 00:13:20,190 So a subset of this 15 percent has actually been able to use the mental imagery task to communicate as well. 129 00:13:20,190 --> 00:13:24,300 So in a paper in 2010 by Martin Montie and colleagues, 130 00:13:24,300 --> 00:13:30,690 they asked one of the patients who was really good at command following a series of yes or no questions. 131 00:13:30,690 --> 00:13:35,090 So they would ask him, is your name X? And the answer is yes. 132 00:13:35,090 --> 00:13:38,000 Imagine playing tennis. And if the answer is no. Imagine walking through your house. 133 00:13:38,000 --> 00:13:43,000 And so he was able to do this, use mental energy to communicate in kind of this basic. 134 00:13:43,000 --> 00:13:50,520 sort of way. So on the left, here is Scott Rally. 135 00:13:50,520 --> 00:13:55,260 And he was one of the kind of the first communicators using mental imagery. 136 00:13:55,260 --> 00:14:06,000 And on the right is Jeff Trombley. He was the first one to demonstrate awareness to the movie task, which I'll talk about a little bit later. 137 00:14:06,000 --> 00:14:20,300 So today, the vast majority of patients who have been able to demonstrate covert awareness have have had been what we would call chronic. 138 00:14:20,300 --> 00:14:25,340 Chronic disorders of consciousness. So it's only after several months or in that Scott's case, 139 00:14:25,340 --> 00:14:34,010 several years of being in what was considered a vegetative state, that they were able to demonstrate their awareness. 140 00:14:34,010 --> 00:14:38,030 So these patients were, as a general rule, physiologically stable. 141 00:14:38,030 --> 00:14:42,590 They were living in launch long term care or living at home with family members. 142 00:14:42,590 --> 00:14:52,520 So at this time, months or years after their injury, further recovery was pretty unlikely, although not necessarily impossible. 143 00:14:52,520 --> 00:15:01,940 There have been a handful of cases where someone has made a full recovery even after being in a vegetative state for for several months. 144 00:15:01,940 --> 00:15:07,700 But importantly for this discussion at this kind of chronic stage, end of life, 145 00:15:07,700 --> 00:15:12,320 kind of decisions tend not to be at the forefront for surrogate decision makers. 146 00:15:12,320 --> 00:15:18,790 So decisions about whether we're going to pursue aggressive treatment, such as brain surgery or whether going to war, 147 00:15:18,790 --> 00:15:24,290 whether we're going to insert a trick he asked me to or whether we're going to insert feeding tubes or things like that. 148 00:15:24,290 --> 00:15:29,290 These decisions are made kind of within the first 10 days of the first two weeks after injury. 149 00:15:29,290 --> 00:15:32,000 So for chronic patients like Jeff and Scott, 150 00:15:32,000 --> 00:15:39,020 the discovery of covert awareness probably wasn't going to make a huge difference to treatment decisions. 151 00:15:39,020 --> 00:15:46,340 Obviously, it's going to be important for lots of other reasons having to do with how we understand the welfare of these patients. 152 00:15:46,340 --> 00:15:52,910 But as far as treatment decisions, it probably doesn't make a huge difference. And so, not surprisingly, 153 00:15:52,910 --> 00:15:58,610 kind of discussions about whether we would whether these patients would now be withdrawn 154 00:15:58,610 --> 00:16:04,070 from treatment or whether this provided kind of a further motivation to keep them alive. 155 00:16:04,070 --> 00:16:10,370 This is sort of not at the forefront for for surrogate decision makers kind of at this stage. 156 00:16:10,370 --> 00:16:18,050 However, it is at the forefront of thinking for patients and families in the acute stages after brain injury. 157 00:16:18,050 --> 00:16:27,410 So just the idea that potentially 15 percent of patients that are diagnosed as agitated might actually kind of covertly aware. 158 00:16:27,410 --> 00:16:34,000 That really complicates surrogate decision making. 159 00:16:34,000 --> 00:16:44,520 So, as I mentioned before, the potential for recovery within disorders of consciousness decline's kind of over time. 160 00:16:44,520 --> 00:16:53,360 So after a traumatic brain injury, it's very, very unlikely that a patient's going to recover consciousness 12 months after their injury. 161 00:16:53,360 --> 00:16:58,980 And for an anoxic brain injury, it's very, very uncommon for them to recover consciousness. 162 00:16:58,980 --> 00:17:06,930 Three months after the brain injury, but, of course, waiting this amount of time for things to become a bit more certain. 163 00:17:06,930 --> 00:17:10,410 It also eliminates certain kinds of treatment decisions that you might make. 164 00:17:10,410 --> 00:17:16,050 So usually withdrawal decisions are made kind of within the first few days. 165 00:17:16,050 --> 00:17:23,110 I think one study suggested that after brain injury, I think it was 50 percent of. 166 00:17:23,110 --> 00:17:26,890 Patients that were withdrawn were withdrawn within the first 72 hours. 167 00:17:26,890 --> 00:17:32,740 So usually these decisions are made quite early when things are very uncertain because we just don't 168 00:17:32,740 --> 00:17:38,180 know how these patients are going to do and kind of what their trajectory for recovery is going to be. 169 00:17:38,180 --> 00:17:46,630 And now when you throw into the mix this idea that, well, 50 percent of these patients might actually be conscious already or 50 percent 170 00:17:46,630 --> 00:17:51,280 of patients who appear to lack consciousness might actually be conscious. 171 00:17:51,280 --> 00:17:58,270 You can see how this would complicate decision making for surrogate decision makers. 172 00:17:58,270 --> 00:18:05,830 So, unfortunately, functional neuro imaging to detect over to where this is not sort of widely available right now. 173 00:18:05,830 --> 00:18:11,140 It only occurs at a handful of research institutions around the world. 174 00:18:11,140 --> 00:18:16,210 So this is not something that is accessible at kind of the typical hospital. 175 00:18:16,210 --> 00:18:19,030 So right now, it's only accessible in a research context. 176 00:18:19,030 --> 00:18:26,770 I'm part of that's due to sort of the expertise that's required to administer these kinds of tests and interpret the results. 177 00:18:26,770 --> 00:18:31,950 Part of it is due to just the lack of availability of MRI. 178 00:18:31,950 --> 00:18:40,810 So research, great f MRI, a potential resolution to this latter concern, as is the use of EEG and F years. 179 00:18:40,810 --> 00:18:46,930 That's electro Ancef, several graphy and functional near Infra-Red spectroscopy. 180 00:18:46,930 --> 00:18:55,420 These are other ways that we can assess consciousness so we can do kind of mental imagery with these other modalities. 181 00:18:55,420 --> 00:19:02,410 And these are portable. So these can be done at the bedside. So reduce the risk of moving patients around and and putting them in the scanner. 182 00:19:02,410 --> 00:19:11,650 So potentially using your imaging to assess COGAT awareness might become more widespread in the near future. 183 00:19:11,650 --> 00:19:18,010 But it was only in twenty eighteen that the American Academy of Neurology updated its practise guidelines and said 184 00:19:18,010 --> 00:19:28,610 that using functional MRI imaging was appropriate method of assessing the kind of Kovar awareness in patients. 185 00:19:28,610 --> 00:19:33,070 So prior to then, this was not something that they that they recommended doing. 186 00:19:33,070 --> 00:19:38,650 And now it's acceptable to do when there is kind of ambiguity with behavioural tests. 187 00:19:38,650 --> 00:19:48,100 So there's still a little bit of scepticism still about making this kind of a standard part of a diagnosis for these patients. 188 00:19:48,100 --> 00:19:53,440 But there's reason to think that it might become more spread, more widespread in the near future. 189 00:19:53,440 --> 00:20:01,480 But it's important to remember that oftentimes functionally imaging is going to return a negative finding. 190 00:20:01,480 --> 00:20:08,000 So, as I said, about 50 percent of patients that are scanned are able to demonstrate Kober awareness. 191 00:20:08,000 --> 00:20:14,200 That means that what? Eighty five percent don't demonstrate any evidence of covert awareness. 192 00:20:14,200 --> 00:20:19,390 However, that doesn't mean that they are conscious. It just means that they weren't able to do make a living. 193 00:20:19,390 --> 00:20:25,240 So it is possible that a patient could still be conscious, but they just weren't able to do the task. 194 00:20:25,240 --> 00:20:30,870 Because as it turns out, less than one hundred percent of healthy undergraduates aren't able to do mental imagery. 195 00:20:30,870 --> 00:20:42,540 So maybe that means that they are actually conscious. But more likely, it means that sometimes we get false negatives using this kind of test. 196 00:20:42,540 --> 00:20:51,150 OK, so the big question here that I want to talk about today, how should surrogates make decisions on behalf of behaviourally nonresponsive patients? 197 00:20:51,150 --> 00:20:57,180 So given that there is this uncertain trajectory and given that some patients might be covertly aware, 198 00:20:57,180 --> 00:21:03,750 but we don't know which ones they are, we really don't have a good sense of what life is like for these kinds of patients. 199 00:21:03,750 --> 00:21:05,310 They could be suffering. 200 00:21:05,310 --> 00:21:14,520 It could be that they may turn out to live an acceptable life if we just sort of give them enough time to declare themselves and keep them alive. 201 00:21:14,520 --> 00:21:20,520 Or maybe, like I say, they are experiencing sort of profound suffering. 202 00:21:20,520 --> 00:21:25,880 So given all of this uncertainty, what what should surrogate decision makers do? 203 00:21:25,880 --> 00:21:33,070 It's a difficult question. We'll try and get a bit of clarity. 204 00:21:33,070 --> 00:21:40,920 OK. So the standard view of surrogate decisions being adopted in sort of most legal statute uses a hierarchical framework. 205 00:21:40,920 --> 00:21:47,610 So the first thing that one ought to do as a surrogate decision maker is appeal to any advanced directives that exist. 206 00:21:47,610 --> 00:21:55,460 So when a formerly competent patient expresses a clear preference for or against a certain intervention. 207 00:21:55,460 --> 00:21:58,260 And they articulate this, an advance directive, the surrogate. 208 00:21:58,260 --> 00:22:03,120 Basically, all they have to do is see that his preferences is here to as much as possible. 209 00:22:03,120 --> 00:22:09,330 So if I write out I don't want one, under no circumstances do I want the tracheostomy, 210 00:22:09,330 --> 00:22:15,030 then my surrogate decision maker just needs to say, well, we don't we don't want to do that one. 211 00:22:15,030 --> 00:22:20,820 When the physician asks, should be, should we kind of go down that road? 212 00:22:20,820 --> 00:22:27,900 In many cases, however, there is no advance directive. People don't tend to write advance directives that often. 213 00:22:27,900 --> 00:22:33,870 So when no advance directive exists, the task of the surrogate is to make a substitute judgement on their behalf. 214 00:22:33,870 --> 00:22:42,750 So basically what they have to do is decide, as the patient would have decided for themselves in the circumstances if they were competent. 215 00:22:42,750 --> 00:22:47,090 So they kind of have to reconstruct sort of what the patient's motivations would have been. 216 00:22:47,090 --> 00:22:52,330 And the decision that they would have made for themselves if they could. So when a substitute judgement, 217 00:22:52,330 --> 00:23:01,310 is it possible either because we just don't know what the patient would have wanted or because there's no one around that really knows them? 218 00:23:01,310 --> 00:23:05,340 We we kind of fall to the the best interest standard, 219 00:23:05,340 --> 00:23:10,380 so we just make the decision that we think in a general sort of way would be in the patient's best interest. 220 00:23:10,380 --> 00:23:16,860 So this appeals to kind of a general conception of interest that most people could be expected to have the right. 221 00:23:16,860 --> 00:23:23,160 We are concerned about minimising suffering or we think most people would be concerned about restoring physical capacity. 222 00:23:23,160 --> 00:23:31,800 So we make decisions with an eye to restoring physical capacity, just sort of based on what a reasonable person would probably want for themselves. 223 00:23:31,800 --> 00:23:38,980 So it's a little less tailored to sort of the individual preferences of of the patient. 224 00:23:38,980 --> 00:23:43,860 OK. So that's the standard view. But in practise as surrogate decision making. 225 00:23:43,860 --> 00:23:48,120 Perhaps not surprisingly, often departs from the standard model. 226 00:23:48,120 --> 00:23:55,830 So surrogates will engage in conversations with physicians about what the patient's prognosis is and the possibility of their recovery or decline. 227 00:23:55,830 --> 00:24:02,820 They will weigh kind of the burdens of continued treatment on the patient. So he's the patient suffering physically, emotionally, mentally. 228 00:24:02,820 --> 00:24:12,250 What is their anticipated quality of life? So all of these are important considerations in sort of informing best interest or substituting judgement. 229 00:24:12,250 --> 00:24:17,580 But surrogates also sometimes will draw on beliefs about the patient's personality. 230 00:24:17,580 --> 00:24:27,030 So they might say things like, well, you know, Frieda was a real fighter and she wouldn't want us to give up on her or Frieda was very religious. 231 00:24:27,030 --> 00:24:29,380 And so she believed in sort of the preciousness of life. 232 00:24:29,380 --> 00:24:37,540 And so she would want us to continue going or free to believe that, you know, God would take care, take care of her. 233 00:24:37,540 --> 00:24:42,990 So we don't we don't want sort of medical technological kind of intervention. 234 00:24:42,990 --> 00:24:48,300 Surrogates might also consider a sort of the burdens on themselves or other members of 235 00:24:48,300 --> 00:24:53,100 the patient's family in deciding what would what would be best or they might think, 236 00:24:53,100 --> 00:24:58,730 well, what would I want in this situation if I was the patient? So, again, they're not making kind of a substitute judgement. 237 00:24:58,730 --> 00:25:06,680 They're thinking. What they would sort of prefer and using that to kind of inform their decision. 238 00:25:06,680 --> 00:25:10,880 So in reality, surrogate decision making is in practise. 239 00:25:10,880 --> 00:25:19,880 I should say it's kind of a mishmash of a whole bunch of different strategies, but there isn't really one sort of clear formula of that. 240 00:25:19,880 --> 00:25:29,960 Families tend to follow, and this can lead to conflicts and uncertainty about what to do either amongst families or between them. 241 00:25:29,960 --> 00:25:37,010 So adhering to the standard view of surrogate decision making does provide one way of resolving the conflict. 242 00:25:37,010 --> 00:25:41,750 So surrogate should make a substitute substituted judgement, a free this case. 243 00:25:41,750 --> 00:25:49,250 So based on the fact that she said she wouldn't want to live in a severely disabled state, she expressed this preference fairly clearly. 244 00:25:49,250 --> 00:25:57,050 What we ought to do is adhere to it and stop treating her. 245 00:25:57,050 --> 00:26:03,120 So I'm going to argue that the standard view of surrogate decision making has some flaws. 246 00:26:03,120 --> 00:26:09,560 The substituted judgement standard specifically assumes that once a patient uses decision making capacity, 247 00:26:09,560 --> 00:26:12,110 their past values and wishes become overheated. 248 00:26:12,110 --> 00:26:18,620 So what we need to do once a patient loses the capacity to make decisions for themselves is to think about what they 249 00:26:18,620 --> 00:26:25,170 wanted in the past or what they expressed in the past and and use that to sort of construct what we should do now. 250 00:26:25,170 --> 00:26:32,690 So I propose that a person can lose decision making capacity, but still retain sufficient mental capacities to allow them to have meaningful values 251 00:26:32,690 --> 00:26:37,040 and interest in these values and interests that should guide to a good decision, 252 00:26:37,040 --> 00:26:46,130 not necessarily their past. So I don't want to argue that past wishes or preferences or things like that are never relevant. 253 00:26:46,130 --> 00:26:52,730 I'm not arguing that we should never look to patients prior wishes or their advance records to decide what we should do. 254 00:26:52,730 --> 00:27:00,530 I think in some cases you should do that. I just want to more question why we tend to draw the line at the loss of decision making capacity. 255 00:27:00,530 --> 00:27:11,780 So why is it that once a patient decision making capacity, we care much, much less about their present interests or values? 256 00:27:11,780 --> 00:27:17,730 And we care much, much more about what they wanted in the past. So I want to question that. 257 00:27:17,730 --> 00:27:23,790 And then I want to go on to or how this might apply in cases of CND and I'll argue that patients 258 00:27:23,790 --> 00:27:29,310 with CND retain sufficient mental capacity to continue to have values and interests in the present, 259 00:27:29,310 --> 00:27:34,680 despite lacking Decision-Making capacity. OK. 260 00:27:34,680 --> 00:27:44,070 So any of you who are interested in medical ethics, you know that in Western medical ethics at least, is a very high value placed on digital autonomy. 261 00:27:44,070 --> 00:27:47,510 So because the burden of treatment is primarily borne by the patients, 262 00:27:47,510 --> 00:27:52,350 we think that patients have the right to choose which treatments they will and won't accept. 263 00:27:52,350 --> 00:27:56,220 So Surrogate Decision-Making kind of starts from this basic starting point. 264 00:27:56,220 --> 00:28:01,560 So when a patient can't be relied upon to make decisions for themselves about their treatment, 265 00:28:01,560 --> 00:28:07,230 how can we project their general right to make their own decisions? So if we can't decide for ourselves and the president, 266 00:28:07,230 --> 00:28:13,830 how can we sort of respect the importance of individual autonomy in decision making on their behalf? 267 00:28:13,830 --> 00:28:22,920 So we ask ourselves, what would the patient decide for themselves? I mean, this is a natural strategy to look at what the patient's prior wishes were, 268 00:28:22,920 --> 00:28:29,100 what they express when they were so competent and kind of build from that prior stage of companies. 269 00:28:29,100 --> 00:28:40,810 What we should do for them in the present. So our best alternative is to appeal to the choices that they made in the past. 270 00:28:40,810 --> 00:28:48,400 A highly influential articulation of this view comes from Dworkin in the book Lies to Me. 271 00:28:48,400 --> 00:28:53,000 So we'll talk a little bit more about working in his view of the economy. 272 00:28:53,000 --> 00:29:00,350 So for Dworkin well-being, our well-being depends on experiential interests and critical interest. 273 00:29:00,350 --> 00:29:06,140 So experiential interests are those things that value because we like the experience of doing them. 274 00:29:06,140 --> 00:29:12,110 So these are things that we think are exciting or enjoyable or pleasure. Also, it doesn't track perfectly with wisdom, find pleasurable. 275 00:29:12,110 --> 00:29:17,990 But these are things that we can join. We just kind of for the sake of doing. 276 00:29:17,990 --> 00:29:25,010 Critical interests, on the other hand, are concerned with things that we believe are generally genuinely important for a good life. 277 00:29:25,010 --> 00:29:31,690 So critical interests kind of capture what we think is really valuable and about what we should want from our lives. 278 00:29:31,690 --> 00:29:33,950 And if we didn't have these things, we'd be much worse off. 279 00:29:33,950 --> 00:29:44,880 So I might have an experience or interest in playing golf or hanging out with my my friends, because this is just something that I like to do. 280 00:29:44,880 --> 00:29:55,080 It makes me happy. It gives me pleasure. Conversely, having a sort of a good relationship with my siblings might be a critical interest. 281 00:29:55,080 --> 00:30:01,790 I think it's really important for a good life to have a good relationship with one's family or something like that. 282 00:30:01,790 --> 00:30:07,960 And in fact, people who don't have a good relationship with their family are sort of less well off. 283 00:30:07,960 --> 00:30:14,060 They're missing something that's important for a good life. So this is this is something about what's really valuable. 284 00:30:14,060 --> 00:30:20,450 I don't I don't like having a relationship with my family because it necessarily makes you happy, although it does. 285 00:30:20,450 --> 00:30:25,490 But the reason I'm doing it is because I think it's something that's genuinely important. 286 00:30:25,490 --> 00:30:31,610 So not only do we want to have sort of the right experiential interests and critical interests under work view, 287 00:30:31,610 --> 00:30:38,360 we also want these interest to be satisfied in the right way. Specifically, we want these things to kind of form a cohesive narrative. 288 00:30:38,360 --> 00:30:43,250 We want our experience to be ordered and the right kind of way to put this another way. 289 00:30:43,250 --> 00:30:49,070 We want to be on to work and to the authors of our own life. 290 00:30:49,070 --> 00:30:56,810 So it's in pursuing kind of critical interests that we that our decisions are shaped and we sort of construct the narrative shape of our life. 291 00:30:56,810 --> 00:31:03,410 So we want our lives to have the right kind of experiences and achievements, but we want them to have a certain kind of integrity. 292 00:31:03,410 --> 00:31:11,900 So in expressing our critical interests, we're sort of constructing the kind of people that we think we ought to be. 293 00:31:11,900 --> 00:31:19,010 So we're sort of forming this this coherent sort of narrative of ourselves, and we're living this out through our critical interest. 294 00:31:19,010 --> 00:31:26,600 So I think it's important for people to have good relations with their family and that kind of structures a lot of the decisions that I make. 295 00:31:26,600 --> 00:31:36,860 And this is why it's important for me to have autonomy, because it's through exercising my aton that I am able to sort of express my critical interest 296 00:31:36,860 --> 00:31:42,730 or satisfy my critical interests and sort of create this coherent narrative structure. 297 00:31:42,730 --> 00:31:47,400 And so one of the ways that we can see the importance of this sort of life 298 00:31:47,400 --> 00:31:54,210 narrative is actually when people are talking about the ends of their lives. 299 00:31:54,210 --> 00:31:58,740 So when people talk about kind of dying with dignity or, you know, 300 00:31:58,740 --> 00:32:06,000 I wouldn't want people to see me in a hospital bed or full of tubes surrounded by machines, 301 00:32:06,000 --> 00:32:12,870 because that's not the kind of person that I sort of want to be remembered as. So that's not the sort of person I see myself as E! 302 00:32:12,870 --> 00:32:18,150 So as much as we want our lives to fall, this sort of appropriate life narrative, 303 00:32:18,150 --> 00:32:22,410 we also want our guest to be kind of an appropriate last chapter to our life near. 304 00:32:22,410 --> 00:32:26,730 We want things to be sort of consistent across our lives with this sense of self that 305 00:32:26,730 --> 00:32:32,880 we created over the course of our lives and by living out our critical interests. 306 00:32:32,880 --> 00:32:39,210 So it's important for for work, and this is why autonomy is important and it's important that we're able to choose for ourselves, 307 00:32:39,210 --> 00:32:45,630 not because we're necessarily going to make the best decisions with respect to our well-being. 308 00:32:45,630 --> 00:32:53,040 In fact, he acknowledges that sometimes, well, oftentimes we make decisions that aren't in our best interests. 309 00:32:53,040 --> 00:32:58,440 The importance of autonomy for working is that it allows us to sort of author our own lives. 310 00:32:58,440 --> 00:33:02,310 And that's why we really think autonomy is important. 311 00:33:02,310 --> 00:33:08,160 So once we leave our decision making capacity, we lose this power to author our own self narrative. 312 00:33:08,160 --> 00:33:16,500 So we can't really once we lose our decisionmaking capacity, we lose this sort of sense of ourselves and lose this coherent sense of self. 313 00:33:16,500 --> 00:33:23,040 And our decisions don't really kind of help to construct this narrative anymore. 314 00:33:23,040 --> 00:33:25,530 And at this time, once we lose decision making varsity, 315 00:33:25,530 --> 00:33:33,770 others don't need to sort of adhere to the decisions that we make because they're no longer autonomous decision. 316 00:33:33,770 --> 00:33:43,820 However, we still have a way to sort of preserve people's sort of self narrative, even after they've lost Decision-Making capacity. 317 00:33:43,820 --> 00:33:50,360 And we can do this by appealing to their past decisions. So decision that they made when they were competent so we can allow them to 318 00:33:50,360 --> 00:33:54,000 continue to sort of authored their own lives by appealing to their past decisions. 319 00:33:54,000 --> 00:33:57,260 And this is what Dworking calls precedent. 320 00:33:57,260 --> 00:34:04,190 So by respecting a person's precedent, autonomy, we allow them to shape their life narrative in the way that they did when they were competent. 321 00:34:04,190 --> 00:34:13,570 Not by respecting the decisions that they make now, but the decisions that they made in the past when they were still fully competent. 322 00:34:13,570 --> 00:34:18,910 So importantly, we ought to do this even if it appears to conflict with their best interests in the present. 323 00:34:18,910 --> 00:34:25,390 So even if honouring on incompetence, patient's past decisions, conflicts with what appears to be in their best interests, 324 00:34:25,390 --> 00:34:37,020 now we should side with their past interests because these are the interests that help to construct that life narrative that's that's so important. 325 00:34:37,020 --> 00:34:43,050 OK, so the best way to respect the president's autonomy is through an advanced directive says working in this. 326 00:34:43,050 --> 00:34:48,690 This seems to make sense if what we care about is sort of preserving a life narrative. 327 00:34:48,690 --> 00:34:54,060 Why not appeal to people's wishes and preferences that they wrote down? 328 00:34:54,060 --> 00:35:01,770 Unfortunately, only about 25 percent of people actually have advanced directives in the year, typically elderly people. 329 00:35:01,770 --> 00:35:06,670 So this wouldn't really apply to a lot of the kind of patients that we're talking about now. 330 00:35:06,670 --> 00:35:11,010 See these patients, because these tend to be sort of younger, middle aged patients. 331 00:35:11,010 --> 00:35:18,870 These are the kinds of people that tend to survive severe traumatic brain injury. And so they're unlikely to have advanced directives. 332 00:35:18,870 --> 00:35:23,730 Sort of a more general problem is that event directors often don't contain any meaningful information. 333 00:35:23,730 --> 00:35:30,840 So they're purposely drawn to try to cover as many possible situations as they can. 334 00:35:30,840 --> 00:35:37,170 But because they're so broad, we lose something in terms of specificity. 335 00:35:37,170 --> 00:35:50,140 So. Well, an advance directive might say something like you wouldn't want to have sort of a feeding tubes inserted into your body for any reason. 336 00:35:50,140 --> 00:35:55,480 What if this was only required for two days or something like that? 337 00:35:55,480 --> 00:36:00,520 So that level, that kind of granularity isn't always there in advance directives. 338 00:36:00,520 --> 00:36:05,590 Perhaps more problematically is that adventure executives are often uninformed. 339 00:36:05,590 --> 00:36:13,900 So people are filling them out. Studies indicate that they're they're quite susceptible to change over time. 340 00:36:13,900 --> 00:36:19,690 So what people articulate in advance directive tends to be just what they're feeling at the time. 341 00:36:19,690 --> 00:36:26,520 So it's not like. There's a lot of reflection that goes into this before the advance active is kind of created. 342 00:36:26,520 --> 00:36:32,190 It is sort of a time capsule, so to speak, of people's treatment preferences at a certain time. 343 00:36:32,190 --> 00:36:36,990 So there's we might be unsure about whether this reflects what the person would 344 00:36:36,990 --> 00:36:47,870 actually want when the time comes to to appeal to the advanced directive. 345 00:36:47,870 --> 00:36:53,240 So like advance directives I substituted, judgement is also taken to support precedent, 346 00:36:53,240 --> 00:36:58,400 autonomy, but it's susceptible to similar kinds of practical problems. 347 00:36:58,400 --> 00:37:03,980 So it has difficulty accounting for changes in people's preferences over time. 348 00:37:03,980 --> 00:37:10,760 So I might think sort of now that I wouldn't want to live with a severe disability, 349 00:37:10,760 --> 00:37:16,940 but then I'd become friends with someone with a severe disability and I get to see sort of what life is actually like for them. 350 00:37:16,940 --> 00:37:23,780 And I think, well, maybe being severely disabled wouldn't be as bad as I thought, or maybe I'd become severely disabled. 351 00:37:23,780 --> 00:37:28,340 And then I think, well, actually, being severely disabled isn't as bad as I thought. 352 00:37:28,340 --> 00:37:33,400 I do definitely change my preference from what it was before. 353 00:37:33,400 --> 00:37:39,530 So substituted judgement has some difficulty accounting for these changes and preferences. 354 00:37:39,530 --> 00:37:45,170 Surrogates also have a difficulty identifying where their own needs and values differ from those of the patients. 355 00:37:45,170 --> 00:37:54,780 So this is something that I kind of mentioned before. Introducing another party into the decision making introduces lots of sources of error and bias. 356 00:37:54,780 --> 00:38:01,430 So surrogates, they might not be able to clearly separate what the patient would have, 357 00:38:01,430 --> 00:38:10,310 would have decided what would be best for them versus what the surrogate kind of thinks that the patient would have decided. 358 00:38:10,310 --> 00:38:13,880 Surrogates are also susceptible to certain kinds of biases. 359 00:38:13,880 --> 00:38:22,490 So, for example, the status quo bias is where people just tend to not want to make any changes to treatment. 360 00:38:22,490 --> 00:38:28,130 So we don't want to withdraw and we just sort of let things stay as they are so that we don't have to make a decision. 361 00:38:28,130 --> 00:38:35,960 So this often happens in the cases, in cases of substituted judgement. So, again, by introducing another party, kind of introducing sources of error, 362 00:38:35,960 --> 00:38:45,230 bias and studies suggest next surrogates are only correct in sort of determining what a patient would want. 363 00:38:45,230 --> 00:38:51,410 About 60 percent of the time. So in these sorts of studies, we ask one person to say, you know what? 364 00:38:51,410 --> 00:38:54,660 What they would want in certain circumstances. 365 00:38:54,660 --> 00:39:02,450 Then we ask them, their surrogate decision maker, you kind of guess what they would have wanted and they only match up about 60 percent of the time. 366 00:39:02,450 --> 00:39:08,840 Of course, this is not a perfect measure of how surrogates actually work kind of in practise, 367 00:39:08,840 --> 00:39:19,330 but it suggests that surrogate decision making is by no means 100 percent accurate. 368 00:39:19,330 --> 00:39:26,150 OK. But I think there is in addition to these sorts of practical problems that you think maybe we can resolve with more 369 00:39:26,150 --> 00:39:34,160 education about the importance of advance directives or the kind of more more counselling for surrogate decision makers. 370 00:39:34,160 --> 00:39:39,980 These are sort of practical problems. We could get over. I think there's a deeper problem here. 371 00:39:39,980 --> 00:39:48,380 So recall that on the standard you the value of autonomy is grounded in the importance of being the author of one's own self narrative. 372 00:39:48,380 --> 00:39:54,680 So once a decision making capacity is lost, a person can't be a self author anymore. 373 00:39:54,680 --> 00:40:02,570 So we have to appeal to their past decisions and values. So a paradigm case of this is patients with advanced Alzheimer's. 374 00:40:02,570 --> 00:40:06,650 So these patients at a certain point have lost decision making capacity. 375 00:40:06,650 --> 00:40:09,710 And this has taken to be roughly contemporaneous with the loss. 376 00:40:09,710 --> 00:40:16,520 The kind of global loss of the ability to conceive of their critical interests so they no longer have this coherent sense of themselves. 377 00:40:16,520 --> 00:40:23,390 And they they can't sort of act out of kind of a genuine character anymore. 378 00:40:23,390 --> 00:40:30,260 So they've lost this sense of sort of who and who they are and what motivates kind of their their critical interests. 379 00:40:30,260 --> 00:40:35,510 And this happens at around the time that they lose Decision-Making capacity. 380 00:40:35,510 --> 00:40:41,360 And so the reason that losing decision making capacity is so important is because now they can't kind of author their own lives anymore. 381 00:40:41,360 --> 00:40:46,490 And this is why it's important to immediately move to consideration of their past interests, 382 00:40:46,490 --> 00:40:53,000 to allow them to kind of continue to offer their author their lives, because that's what we think is really important. 383 00:40:53,000 --> 00:40:57,620 So I want to suggest that patients with CNB are likely. 384 00:40:57,620 --> 00:41:05,640 I mean, we don't know this for sure because it would be quite difficult to verify but would likely have lost decision making capacity. 385 00:41:05,640 --> 00:41:13,080 But it seems possible that they still have the kinds of preferences and values which we think should shape decision making on their behalf. 386 00:41:13,080 --> 00:41:18,780 So they may have the capacity for genuine commitments even after losing Decision-Making capacity. 387 00:41:18,780 --> 00:41:23,700 So they might enjoy or genuinely value being part of a family group. 388 00:41:23,700 --> 00:41:29,040 They might value participating in scientific research and sort of benefiting future patients, 389 00:41:29,040 --> 00:41:33,510 even though they lack the capacity to make specific decisions about these kinds of things. 390 00:41:33,510 --> 00:41:42,840 So we wouldn't say to Scott, do you sort of consent to participating in this neuro imaging study because you don't think he has decision making? 391 00:41:42,840 --> 00:41:47,580 What this doesn't mean that he doesn't get sort of some value out of contributing to science, 392 00:41:47,580 --> 00:41:52,410 even if we don't think he could make a specific decision about this for himself. 393 00:41:52,410 --> 00:41:57,630 So these kinds of values don't seem to have anything to do with our life narrative. 394 00:41:57,630 --> 00:42:07,600 But they do seem genuinely important. So there's sort of a minor objection to the work and then a major objection to the work. 395 00:42:07,600 --> 00:42:12,490 To be honest, I'm not I'm not 100 percent sure which one I really want to make here. 396 00:42:12,490 --> 00:42:15,760 So the minor objection seems to be something like this. 397 00:42:15,760 --> 00:42:22,450 Maybe seeing these patients actually do still have something like decision making capacity, even though this is something we don't know. 398 00:42:22,450 --> 00:42:24,370 We can't really know. 399 00:42:24,370 --> 00:42:31,090 So in this case, the best thing to do to reflect their life near that would be to emphasise their present concerns whenever this happens. 400 00:42:31,090 --> 00:42:39,190 So really, the tension is between their past life narrative and the present life near. 401 00:42:39,190 --> 00:42:44,750 So I think Dorkin could maybe accommodate this because we're still sort of privileging the importance of life narrative. 402 00:42:44,750 --> 00:42:49,870 And the question is just how best that he thinks that it's the best way to do that. 403 00:42:49,870 --> 00:42:59,080 So a few of the past decisions, and I would suggest that maybe the best way to accommodate that is to deal with present sort of values. 404 00:42:59,080 --> 00:43:07,480 But ultimately, we're kind of agreeing that life here is important or sort of a primary importance or the more significant objection is that, 405 00:43:07,480 --> 00:43:12,000 look, life narrative is not the only reason that we care about autonomy. 406 00:43:12,000 --> 00:43:18,460 So even if CND patients don't have the capacity to continue to author their 407 00:43:18,460 --> 00:43:26,350 life narrative because they don't have this coherent sense of self anymore, surely they still have the kinds of values and interests that we think are 408 00:43:26,350 --> 00:43:33,130 important and ought to sort of inform ah ah decision making on their behalf. 409 00:43:33,130 --> 00:43:37,510 So forget about the fact that they're no longer the authors of their own lives. 410 00:43:37,510 --> 00:43:43,660 What we should be concerned about is sort of other important values that they might have in the present. 411 00:43:43,660 --> 00:43:47,320 Not so much on their sort of past wishes. 412 00:43:47,320 --> 00:43:54,000 And so this sort of objection would apply not only to see any patients with any kind of patient that lacks Decision-Making capacity. 413 00:43:54,000 --> 00:44:00,680 So is there any evidence for these kind of significant cognitive capacity in patients with CND? 414 00:44:00,680 --> 00:44:06,830 OK. So we said before the mental imagery task requires the exercise of a range of cognitive capacities. 415 00:44:06,830 --> 00:44:13,350 So things like sustained attention and language comprehension, all the things that you need to do to imagine playing tennis. 416 00:44:13,350 --> 00:44:20,210 And some patients have also participated in what I referred to before as the movie task. 417 00:44:20,210 --> 00:44:28,100 So in this in this experiment, patients were just told to widen the scanner and sort of attend to this suspenseful movie. 418 00:44:28,100 --> 00:44:33,000 So this was a short movie clip. I think we call Bang, You're Dead. 419 00:44:33,000 --> 00:44:39,000 And it was a Alfred Hitchcock kind of TV movie. So very quick plot summary, though. 420 00:44:39,000 --> 00:44:44,180 The little boy on the left. He thinks he's playing with a toy gun but he's actually playing with a real gun. 421 00:44:44,180 --> 00:44:48,000 So he's walking around, pointing it at people, pretending to shoot them. 422 00:44:48,000 --> 00:44:55,050 And as a viewer, this is very suspenseful. you think Oh if he actually pulled the trigger, he might kill somebody. 423 00:44:55,050 --> 00:45:05,280 So there's a whole kind of series of experiments. But just to sort of to condense it, basically when a healthy person watches a movie like this, 424 00:45:05,280 --> 00:45:14,160 we see kind of characteristic pattern of activation in various parts of their brain having to do with sort of executive function. 425 00:45:14,160 --> 00:45:22,140 So this is this is a part of the brain. So a kind of system in the brain that allows us to sort of taking visual and auditory information 426 00:45:22,140 --> 00:45:29,910 integrated with our past knowledge to sort of get a sense of the state of play of the world around us. 427 00:45:29,910 --> 00:45:33,240 So help you pick healthy participants when they're watching this suspense movie. 428 00:45:33,240 --> 00:45:36,570 Their brains look like this one. Yes. 429 00:45:36,570 --> 00:45:42,240 Patient their brain with like that. So you would infer from that they were kind of experiencing anything. 430 00:45:42,240 --> 00:45:48,960 So they were getting a little bit of auditory information, but they weren't consciously experiencing anything but another patient. 431 00:45:48,960 --> 00:45:56,670 This is Jeff Trombley. His brain looked very similar to what we would expect from a healthy participant. 432 00:45:56,670 --> 00:46:01,530 So in a series of other kinds of experiments, which I won't get into. 433 00:46:01,530 --> 00:46:10,060 The researchers kind of took this to mean that Jeff was having at least a highly similar conscious experience to a healthy participant. 434 00:46:10,060 --> 00:46:16,110 So he was experiencing the movie in the same way you and I would. So he was experiencing the suspense of the movie. 435 00:46:16,110 --> 00:46:21,480 So what can we infer about his cognitive capacities based on this? 436 00:46:21,480 --> 00:46:28,140 So there's a few different things. One of the most important is that he retains his capacity for executive function so he can take in kind of 437 00:46:28,140 --> 00:46:34,980 sensory information and organise it in this way to sort of understand what's going on in the world around him. 438 00:46:34,980 --> 00:46:38,160 There's also evidence that he possesses sort of a theory of mine. 439 00:46:38,160 --> 00:46:43,770 So he can he can understand that other people are thinking and thinking things that might be different for him. 440 00:46:43,770 --> 00:46:53,610 This is this is critical to understanding that the characters in the movie don't realise that the gun isn't isn't a toy. 441 00:46:53,610 --> 00:46:57,750 So he's able to he's able to understand that other people have thoughts as well. 442 00:46:57,750 --> 00:47:06,000 And perhaps he's capable of organising all of these thoughts into kind of a temporal order in order to follow the plot. 443 00:47:06,000 --> 00:47:12,000 So this is a this is kind of a host of fairly high level cognitive capacities, 444 00:47:12,000 --> 00:47:16,000 which are required to sort of attend to a movie and the same with an healthy person. 445 00:47:16,000 --> 00:47:24,900 So we can infer that these sorts of things are present in at least some CND patients. 446 00:47:24,900 --> 00:47:31,990 So there's some evidence that CND patients may have the kinds of values and interests which ought to inform circuit decision. 447 00:47:31,990 --> 00:47:38,070 Sorry. So I skipped over a little bit there. So the idea is that because they have these sophisticated cognitive capacities, 448 00:47:38,070 --> 00:47:45,340 they have the capacity for certain kinds of values and interests, so similar values and interests. 449 00:47:45,340 --> 00:47:49,020 So because they're capable of organising their thoughts in a certain kind of way, 450 00:47:49,020 --> 00:47:57,330 maybe they have sort of an interest in their lives going in a certain kind of way because they're able to infer thoughts and other people. 451 00:47:57,330 --> 00:48:03,050 This greatly expands kind of how they can how they can understand how people are interacting with them. 452 00:48:03,050 --> 00:48:07,350 And this creates a possibility for different kinds of values and interests as well. 453 00:48:07,350 --> 00:48:10,850 Beyond just self narrative. 454 00:48:10,850 --> 00:48:19,940 So does this make a difference to how surrogate decision makers should actually make decisions on behalf of these patients? 455 00:48:19,940 --> 00:48:23,990 So is there a reason to think that a patient with cognitive motor and dissociation, 456 00:48:23,990 --> 00:48:31,010 if they have these other kinds of if they could potentially have other kinds of important interests, 457 00:48:31,010 --> 00:48:36,890 like an interest in spending time with their family or participating in an important scientific research? 458 00:48:36,890 --> 00:48:41,000 Is there any reason to think that their interests, by and large, are any different than they were pre injury? 459 00:48:41,000 --> 00:48:50,780 So if we think, well, look, on Dworkin's view, someone like Frieda wouldn't have wanted to go on living based on her past wishes. 460 00:48:50,780 --> 00:48:54,530 And as it turns out, she doesn't want to go on living based on her present wishes. 461 00:48:54,530 --> 00:48:57,350 So maybe this doesn't really make a difference. 462 00:48:57,350 --> 00:49:04,310 So is there any reason to think that interest, their interest actually would have changed pre and post injury? 463 00:49:04,310 --> 00:49:10,250 Well, there's some evidence for this. So this is on the left, Tony Clinton and on the right. 464 00:49:10,250 --> 00:49:14,240 Kevin Weller. So these are both our patients in the lock and state. 465 00:49:14,240 --> 00:49:19,860 So locking patients, I take to be an illustration of the potential for response shift. 466 00:49:19,860 --> 00:49:28,370 So this is the idea that people's important preferences and expectations for life can shift significantly over time. 467 00:49:28,370 --> 00:49:38,150 In light of changes to their circumstances. So research suggests that many healthy people wouldn't want to go on living if they were locked in. 468 00:49:38,150 --> 00:49:43,820 So, all right, patients that are locked in are completely conscious. 469 00:49:43,820 --> 00:49:50,030 They're fully cognitively intact, just like you and I, but they're completely incapable of movement usually, 470 00:49:50,030 --> 00:49:54,830 except for kind of movements of the jaw or up and down movements of their eyes. 471 00:49:54,830 --> 00:49:59,870 There are some cases of patients that are sure to truly walk in and they can't move at all. 472 00:49:59,870 --> 00:50:05,310 That's a little bit rarer than sort of classic walk ins. I like these patients are. 473 00:50:05,310 --> 00:50:10,500 So, as I said, about 36, 40 percent of patients wouldn't want to go on living a walk, etc., 474 00:50:10,500 --> 00:50:18,000 but about 40 percent of patients are participants in this study are unsure about whether they want to go on living with walk ins. 475 00:50:18,000 --> 00:50:31,000 However, perhaps surprisingly, one study has shown that 72 percent of patients with locked in syndrome that were surveyed self report as being happy. 476 00:50:31,000 --> 00:50:36,090 So they they think that their lives are going, you know, pretty well. 477 00:50:36,090 --> 00:50:42,630 Not all of them say that they would want to be sort of resuscitated in the event of a heart attack. 478 00:50:42,630 --> 00:50:54,180 A small percentage of them kind of would still think they would consent to euthanasia if it were offered to them, something like five percent of them. 479 00:50:54,180 --> 00:50:58,440 So there are these these statistics should be taken with, I think, 480 00:50:58,440 --> 00:51:06,810 with a pinch of salt so they could reflect a selection bias on these patients were taken from sort of a support group of locked in syndrome patients. 481 00:51:06,810 --> 00:51:09,930 So maybe there was some self selection here. 482 00:51:09,930 --> 00:51:17,810 The kind of patient that one participated in the study about happiness and locked in syndrome tend to be happier. 483 00:51:17,810 --> 00:51:25,590 And on the left, Tony Nicholson was involved in kind of prolonged case about. 484 00:51:25,590 --> 00:51:29,190 Sort of whether it was legal for him to be allowed to die. 485 00:51:29,190 --> 00:51:32,940 So he was not happy in in his in his condition. 486 00:51:32,940 --> 00:51:40,110 And he very much wanted to end his life. So I'm not suggesting that locked in syndrome all locked into Indian patients or happen by any means. 487 00:51:40,110 --> 00:51:47,190 But I am suggesting that this is a case where we might think that, you know, life would be truly awful. 488 00:51:47,190 --> 00:51:51,540 But once we actually get into that situation, maybe it wouldn't be so bad. 489 00:51:51,540 --> 00:51:57,570 So, again, locked in syndrome is very different from calling about an association. 490 00:51:57,570 --> 00:52:02,820 Locking patients do have some capacity for communication, which, 491 00:52:02,820 --> 00:52:10,440 with the exception of the very few patients who have used ephemera to communicate as individuals, by and large, can't communicate. 492 00:52:10,440 --> 00:52:13,980 So there's definitely a difference between those patient groups. 493 00:52:13,980 --> 00:52:20,000 But I just want to suggest that there is the potential that a patient sort of past wishes to 494 00:52:20,000 --> 00:52:25,950 not go on living with a severe kind of disability like CND or like locked in syndrome. 495 00:52:25,950 --> 00:52:32,740 Those actually might change once they're actually in that situation. OK. 496 00:52:32,740 --> 00:52:40,300 So to get back to the main question, how should surrogates make decisions on behalf of behavioural nonresponsive patients? 497 00:52:40,300 --> 00:52:47,350 So I think surrogate decision makers should be cautious about placing too much weight on patients past desires and values. 498 00:52:47,350 --> 00:52:54,000 They should place a greater weight on their present values, concerns and desires, reflecting the ways they can still engage with the world. 499 00:52:54,000 --> 00:53:01,870 So I've argued that there's some evidence that patients with covert Awareness could retain the capacity for critical interest in the present, 500 00:53:01,870 --> 00:53:05,500 i.e. they could have a sense of what's meaningful and valuable in life for them. 501 00:53:05,500 --> 00:53:09,640 And that may be different from their past critical injuries. 502 00:53:09,640 --> 00:53:17,740 So I think this gives a reason to question the authority of their past critical interest in decision making on their behalf. 503 00:53:17,740 --> 00:53:23,710 I think that even if we want to grant that shaping one's life narrative is important. 504 00:53:23,710 --> 00:53:29,170 I don't think it should necessarily be a primary importance because the other kinds of values are important as well. 505 00:53:29,170 --> 00:53:34,570 And these values that these patients can still have are important as well. 506 00:53:34,570 --> 00:53:38,890 So patients pass critical interest may have reflected how they wonder lights go in the past, 507 00:53:38,890 --> 00:53:46,750 but it may not reflect how they want their lives to go in the present. Now, there's no doubt that in the absence of communication with these patients, 508 00:53:46,750 --> 00:53:52,270 it's a it's a significant challenge to sort of discern what actually would be in their best interest in the present. 509 00:53:52,270 --> 00:53:59,830 So what these so I say they might be capable of having certain kinds of values or interests in the present that should govern decision making. 510 00:53:59,830 --> 00:54:07,000 What these desires and values actually are is going to be really hard to determine without direct communication. 511 00:54:07,000 --> 00:54:14,470 So we can make kind of general inferences from similar patients. So like locked in patients. 512 00:54:14,470 --> 00:54:17,080 That's that's one potential option. 513 00:54:17,080 --> 00:54:29,150 There are different kinds of sort of qualitative assessments being developed of well-being in patients with disorders of consciousness. 514 00:54:29,150 --> 00:54:34,310 We should probably think about how these patients are likely to be experiencing their condition right now, 515 00:54:34,310 --> 00:54:38,910 maybe based on the kinds of ways that they reacted to situations in the past. 516 00:54:38,910 --> 00:54:40,460 As there is some evidence to suggest, 517 00:54:40,460 --> 00:54:49,490 the way people feel with kinds of crises or difficulties does sort of transfer over pre and post disability others. 518 00:54:49,490 --> 00:54:51,710 There's no question that it's going to be very difficult. 519 00:54:51,710 --> 00:55:02,450 And I think maybe we need to be open to the possibility that for some patients, continued life is not necessarily going to be in their best interests. 520 00:55:02,450 --> 00:55:09,710 But the but the takeaway is that we should be focussing on their present interest rather than their past wishes. 521 00:55:09,710 --> 00:55:15,530 So obviously, there's a need for continued development, for tools to assess well-being in noncommunicative patients, 522 00:55:15,530 --> 00:55:22,520 because even as the ability to communicate with them grows, the majority of patients probably won't be able to communicate with them directly. 523 00:55:22,520 --> 00:55:31,780 So we need to find some way to kind of get at these these values that are important to them in the present. 524 00:55:31,780 --> 00:55:39,680 OK. Very brief summary. So the standard view of circuit decision making places significant emphasis on respecting patient autonomy. 525 00:55:39,680 --> 00:55:44,400 So when a patient loses competence, their past desires and wishes become authority. 526 00:55:44,400 --> 00:55:47,870 And the reason this is, is because self authorship is really important. 527 00:55:47,870 --> 00:55:53,420 But somewhat authorship isn't the only reason we care about making your own decisions contract working. 528 00:55:53,420 --> 00:55:58,370 So these other considerations, I suggest, ought to inform surrogate decision making. 529 00:55:58,370 --> 00:56:04,850 And CND patients are one example of a patient group that could continue to have these values and interests in the present. 530 00:56:04,850 --> 00:56:13,130 And so when we're thinking about how we should be making decisions on behalf of these patients, we should focus on the present rather than the past. 531 00:56:13,130 --> 00:56:17,420 Thank you very much. All right. 532 00:56:17,420 --> 00:56:20,898 Thank you. We will be here all along, Mackenzie. Oh, you OK?